CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 47 FEBRUARY 2015 NUMBER 3 Article Emotional Duties ERICA GOLDBERG The distinction between physical and emotional harm is fundamental. Legal disciplines from torts to constitutional law rely on a hierarchy that places bodily integrity over emotional tranquility. This hierarchy is now under attack by scientists and scholars. Neuroscientists have undermined the view that emotional harm is more subjective; social scientists have refuted the position that emotional harm is less impactful; and feminist scholars have undercut the view that these categories are gender neutral. Courts are taking notice, especially in tort law, and each new Restatement of Torts provides more avenues for plaintiffs to collect damages for emotional injuries. This Article defends the relevance of the distinction between physical and emotional harm, especially in tort law, by offering theoretical justifications that are responsive to the modern criticisms. A new conception of the distinction should be based on a duty to reasonably regulate one’s own emotional health. This duty fits well within tort theories, including law and economics, corrective justice, and civil recourse theory, and harmonizes with criminal law and First Amendment doctrines. Further, neuroscience, social science, and even feminist theory support this duty. A duty to maintain one’s own emotional well-being can benefit both tort plaintiffs and defendants by incorporating normative ideals about identity, consent, autonomy, social justice, and social welfare. In advancing this emotional duty, this Article also provides sustainable definitions for physical and emotional harm that can survive changing technology, and discusses the implications of a new understanding of the physical/emotional hierarchy for tort law. 809 ARTICLE CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 811 II. TORT LAW’S SELF-CONSCIOUS STRUGGLES WITH THE PHYSICAL/EMOTIONAL DISTINCTION ........................................ 817 A. THE TORTURED PATH OF TORT LAW................................................... 818 B. PARASITIC DAMAGES VS. THE EGGSHELL PSYCHE RULE .................... 822 III. CHALLENGES TO THE PHYSICAL/EMOTIONAL DISTINCTION ..................................................................................... 825 A. MEASURING EMOTIONAL HARM ......................................................... 826 B. VALUING EMOTIONAL HARM .............................................................. 831 C. GENDERING EMOTIONAL HARM .......................................................... 834 IV. RESUSCITATING THE PHYSICAL/EMOTIONAL DISTINCTION ..................................................................................... 841 A. DEFINING THE CATEGORIES ................................................................ 842 B. THE DUTY TO MAINTAIN ONE’S EMOTIONAL HEALTH........................ 847 V. IMPLICATIONS AND DOCTRINAL MODIFICATIONS .................. 869 A. EMOTIONAL DUTIES AND EGGSHELL PSYCHES ................................... 869 B. COMPENSABLE EMOTIONAL INJURIES ................................................. 871 C. PARASITIC PHYSICAL AND EMOTIONAL DAMAGES .............................. 875 VI. CONCLUSION ..................................................................................... 877 Emotional Duties ERICA GOLDBERG∗ I. INTRODUCTION There is a battle between bodies and minds in the law. Many legal doctrines place great weight on whether a particular injury is classified as physical or emotional, generally giving greater protection to the former.1 Recent developments, both in science and legal thought, have cast doubt on this distinction. The foundation for the law’s preferential treatment of physical harm seems to be crumbling, and courts and commentators are taking notice. This Article aims to establish new theoretical justifications for the distinction between physical and emotional harm as it relates to tort law. The distinction should be based on a duty that we all have to reasonably regulate our own emotional well-being—if we seek legal redress. Historically, a sharp divide between physical and emotional harm has dictated the scope of liability for such harms. In tort law, emotional injuries not stemming from physical injuries are considered separate from physical injuries.2 Suits alleging pure emotional injuries face hurdles that suits alleging physical injuries do not, including special limited-duty rules that significantly circumscribe liability.3 Tort law is hardly unique in this respect. First Amendment doctrine likewise relies on the notion that speech that causes emotional harm should be less susceptible to regulation than conduct that causes physical harm.4 The Fifth Amendment prohibits the police from using physical coercion when extracting confessions but ∗ Climenko Fellow and Lecturer on Law, Harvard Law School. I would like to express my gratitude for their helpful comments and insights to I. Glenn Cohen, Sam Datlof, Dan Epps, Richard Fallon, Joseph Fishman, Charles Fried, Maggie Gardner, John Goldberg, Paul Gowder, Jacob Kreutzer, Adriaan Lanni, Charlotte Lawson, Michael Morley, Seth Stoughton, Susannah Barton Tobin, and Matthew Wansley. 1 Precise definitions of physical versus emotional harm will be discussed infra, Part IV. The Restatement (Third) of Torts notes that emotional harm “encompasses a variety of mental states, including fright, fear, sadness, sorrow, despondency, anxiety, humiliation, depression (and other mental illnesses), and a host of other detrimental—from mildly unpleasant to disabling—mental conditions.” RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 45 (2012). 2 Infra Part II. 3 Id. 4 Infra Part IV. 812 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 5 permits many types of deception and emotional manipulation. Criminal law often explicitly distinguishes between physical and emotional injury when defining harms.6 Despite its importance, courts have struggled to explain the physical/emotional distinction, and scholars and scientists are increasingly prone to decry its artificiality.7 Nowhere has this distinction been more sharply criticized than in tort law. Although a few scholars have attempted to explain the distinction,8 or justify it as necessary for reasons of judicial 5 Id. But see Dov Fox & Alex Stein, Dualism and Doctrine, 90 IND. L.J. (forthcoming 2015) (discussing how the Fifth Amendment has been interpreted to privilege the mind over the body in determining what constitutes a self-incrimination violation). 6 Fox & Stein, supra note 5, at 17–18. 7 See, e.g., Martha Chamallas, The Architecture of Bias: Deep Structures in Tort Law, 146 U. PA. L. REV. 463, 499 (1998) (“[L]egal claims for emotional distress have been devalued in part because they are associated with female plaintiffs.”); Martha Chamallas & Linda K. Kerber, Women, Mothers, and the Law of Fright: A History, 88 MICH L. REV. 814, 814 (1990) (reasoning that the physical/emotional dichotomy has “privileged men, as the traditional owners and managers of property, and has burdened women, to whom the emotional work of maintaining human relationships has commonly been assigned”); Fox & Stein, supra note 5, at 10–11, 17, 20–23, 25–27 (criticizing the mind-body dualism in the Supreme Court doctrines of harm, compulsion, and intentionality); Oscar S. Gray, Commentary, Negligent Infliction of Emotional Distress: A View of the Proposed Restatement (Third) Provisions from England, 44 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 1193, 1193 (2009) [hereinafter Commentary] (arguing that, rather than focusing on the physical/emotional distinction, courts should focus on the “distinction between what might be called ‘mere feelings’ on the one hand and ‘injury’ on the other”); Betsy J. Grey, Neuroscience and Emotional Harm in Tort Law: Rethinking the American Approach to Free-Standing Emotional Distress Claims, in 13 LAW AND NEUROSCIENCE: CURRENT LEGAL ISSUES 2010 212 (Michael Freeman ed., 2011) (“Advances in neuroscience suggest that this concern over verification [of emotional distress] may no longer be valid, and that the phenomena we call ‘emotional’ harm has a physiological basis. Because of these early scientific advances, this may be an appropriate time to re-examine our assumptions with regard to tort recovery for emotional harm.”); Nancy Levit, Ethereal Torts, 61 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 136, 175–76 (1992) (arguing that the reluctance to sympathize with and provide redress for emotional injuries is a product of narrow-minded skepticism); Calvert Magruder, Mental and Emotional Disturbance in the Law of Torts, 49 HARV. L. REV. 1033, 1033–35 (1936) (recounting judicial reluctance to provide redress when an unlawful act causes only mental and emotional harm); John T. Nockleby & Shannon Curreri, 100 Years of Conflict: The Past and Future of Tort Retrenchment, 38 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 1021, 1071, 1071 n.213 (2005) (explaining the scientific community’s research “establishing that emotional disturbances were, as a matter of fact, a mixture of physical and mental manifestations”); Geoffrey Christopher Rapp, Defense Against Outrage and the Perils of Parasitic Torts, 45 GA. L. REV. 107, 110 (2010) (explaining the often criticized trend of affording self-defense privileges in connection with the use of physical force). 8 See John C. P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, 88 VA. L. REV. 1625, 1669–70, 1685 (2002) (explaining the “reluctance of the courts to recognize a broad duty to take care to avoid causing emotional distress” based on the “notion of bearing (at least partial) responsibility for one’s own emotional state”). Goldberg and Zipursky’s claim provides a descriptive account about why courts treat physical and emotional harm differently. Id. at 1677–85. However, to the extent that this limited liability for emotional harms fits well within a tort system properly understood as providing plaintiffs with civil recourse for particular wrongs, Goldberg and Zipursky’s position is self-described as “weakly normative.” See John C. P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Civil Recourse Defended: A Reply to Posner, Calabresi, Rustad, Chamallas, and Robinette, 88 IND. L.J. 569, 602 (2013) [hereinafter Goldberg & Zipursky, Civil Recourse Defended] (“To make sense of a body of law that many have assumed to be incoherent is already to recognize a reason for supposing that it is a body of 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 9 813 10 administration, none actually champion it on theoretical grounds, and most are dismissive, if not outright hostile, toward it. The distinction has been criticized as too individualistic,11 anti-feminist,12 and formalist.13 In its place, scholars are proposing new ways to distinguish between compensable and non-compensable injuries.14 Now, scientific developments are shifting the former fault lines of the debate.15 Although brain-scanning technology still has its limitations, neuroscientists have demonstrated that emotional injuries, like physical injuries, have a physiological basis that can increasingly be measured.16 This undermines the claim that emotional harm is too subjective and easy to fake.17 Further, the hierarchy that values bodily integrity over emotional law worth having.”); see also infra Part IV.B (discussing an argument to expand liability for wrongful conduct causing compensable, enduring emotional injuries, a study indicating that emotional health exerts an often-stronger impact on happiness than does physical health, and the contention that our mental experience of the world is the only thing that matters and therefore emotional wellbeing should be afforded primary importance). 9 See Eugene Kontorovich, The Mitigation of Emotional Distress Damages, 68 U. CHI. L. REV. 491, 492 (2001) (arguing that mitigation rules in emotional distress cases are unworkable and suggesting “limiting the availability of emotional distress damages”). Stanley Ingber proposes a middle-ground solution where emotional harms are recognized as legally compensable and thus destigmatized, but plaintiffs receive damages only for the pecuniary losses stemming from emotional injuries. Stanley Ingber, Rethinking Intangible Injuries: A Focus on Remedy, 73 CALIF. L. REV. 772, 783 (1985). 10 Richard Abel opposes the way damages “commodify . . . unique experience” generally, and argues that “damages for intangible injury dehumanize [by] substituting money for compassion, arousing jealousy rather than expressing sympathy, and contributing to a culture that views experience and love as commodities.” Richard Abel, A Critique of American Tort Law, 8 BRIT. J.L. & SOC’Y 199, 207, 210 (1981). 11 Levit, supra note 7, at 176. 12 Chamallas, supra note 7, at 499. 13 Id. at 530 (“We should not accept the basic tort categories as neutral, static, and essential.”). 14 Scholars suggest distinguishing between illusory and enduring injuries, see Cass R. Sunstein, Illusory Losses, 37 J. LEGAL STUD. S157, S164–66 (2008), or medically diagnosed and undiagnosable injuries, Grey, Neuroscience and Emotional Harm in Tort Law, supra note 7, at 225–26. Some claim that, in place of rigid categories, courts should simply assess each type of injury individually. See Chamallas, supra note 7, at 530 (“My quarrel with the current system is that, through reliance on the implicit hierarchies, we are apt to shortcut difficult judgments about which claims deserve legal recognition, simply by presuming that certain types of injuries, on a categorical basis, are less worthy.”). 15 See infra Part III (discussing the developments of the fMRI technique and PET scans to study pain and emotional distress). One scholar has gone as far as arguing that “[a]t a minimum, this ‘emotional’/‘physical’ distinction casts a pall of apparent antiscience over our work and makes us appear obsolete from the outset.” Commentary, supra note 7, at 1193. 16 See infra Part III (explaining that despite the shortcomings of neuroscience, emerging technologies in the field will increasingly enable us to make inferences about individuals’ cognitive experiences with greater precision). 17 The Restatement (Third) of Torts distinguishes between physical and emotional harm by providing that “[t]he essential difference is that bodily harm usually provides objective evidence of its existence and extent while the existence and severity of emotional harm is usually dependent upon the report of the person suffering it or symptoms that are capable of manipulation or multiple 814 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 tranquility has been questioned by social scientists, who plausibly maintain that emotional harm can be just as debilitating as physical harm.18 Scientists’ and scholars’ objections to the physical/emotional distinction are gaining momentum as our nation is becoming increasingly concerned with mental health.19 Each new Restatement expands the duties that we owe to others to avoid causing emotional harm.20 In the courts and in the legislature, the line separating physical and emotional harm is blurring, with mental illness being de-stigmatized and treated as akin to physical harm.21 No state has yet established a general duty of care to prevent emotional harm, like the tort duty that exists for physical harm,22 but few scholars offer theoretical and normative justifications for treating emotional harm differently than physical harm. Resisting the trend toward abolishing the distinction between physical and emotional harm, this Article defends its continued relevance, particularly in tort law. Given our current treatment of physical harm, which I accept as a baseline, this Article addresses how we should treat emotional harm as standard rationales for this distinction erode. Even accepting that emotional harm can be as serious and legitimate as physical harm, it is erroneous to infer that physical and emotional harm should be treated identically in tort and other bodies of law. The law should not treat physical and emotional harm equally simply because they share more features than once believed. What scholars and scientists gloss over is that our responses to emotional harm are more within our control,23 and are explanations.” RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 4 cmt. b (2010). 18 See infra Part III.B (discussing studies demonstrating that emotional health often has a stronger impact on happiness than physical health). 19 Recent high profile school shootings have highlighted America’s mental health problems because many of the killers suffered from mental illness. See Colleen Curry, Newtown Massacre Result of Mental Illness, Access to Guns, Death Obsession, ABC NEWS (Nov. 25, 2013), http://abcnews.go. com/US/newtown-massacre-result-mental-illness-access-guns-death/story?id=21003690 (reporting that the perpetrator of the Newtown, Connecticut school shooting was afflicted by mental illness); Gerald Landsberg, Shootings Show Need for Mental Health Care, CNN OPINION (Sept. 19, 2013, 8:14 AM), http://www.cnn.com/2013/09/18/opinion/landsberg-shootings-mental-health/ (discussing the frequency with which mental illness serves as the backdrop to America’s mass shootings). 20 Levit, supra note 7, at 143–44 (discussing the history of the recognition of emotional harm). 21 Francis X. Shen, Mind, Body, and the Criminal Law, 97 MINN. L. REV. 2036, 2038 (2013) (discussing the increasing sentiment among policymakers and the public that “‘illness of the brain must be treated just like illness anywhere else in the body’” (quoting Robert Pear, House Approves Bill on Mental Health Parity, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 6, 2008, at A14)). 22 Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1673 (“Whereas [tort decisions] long ago announced a general duty to take care not to cause physical harm and illness, no comparable decisions have taken hold with respect to emotional distress.”). Some states, like Montana, have come close, however. See infra Part II (noting that Montana is one of the few states that includes mental injury within the definition of bodily injury). 23 See Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1681 (offering a normative approach that recognizes that “a plaintiff’s agency plays an important role in the generation of 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 815 bound up in notions of identity, voluntariness, and consent. Additionally, protecting emotional well-being compromises important social goals in ways that protecting bodily integrity does not. Further, the physical/emotional distinction has embedded itself implicitly and explicitly into accepted legal doctrine, including normatively desirable doctrines such as robust free speech protections and notions of autonomy, identity, fault, and consent. This new understanding of the basis of the distinction between physical and emotional harm builds on scientific advances in understanding emotional processing. Accordingly, it offers a framework for identifying a duty for individuals to use their rational faculties to overcome emotional disturbances and to seek assistance for their mental infirmities if they wish to use the force of the law to obtain redress.24 In justifying a new version of the physical/emotional distinction, I also offer definitions of emotional and bodily harm that can survive changing technology, respond to the modern critics of the distinction, and explain when emotional harm should be compensable. This Article will begin by discussing the self-conscious struggles of courts contending with the physical/emotional distinction in tort law, including courts’ approaches to “parasitic” damages and “eggshell psyche” cases. It then frames the debate over the physical/emotional distinction by presenting the views of scientists and scholars who argue in favor of abolishing it. They challenge the scientific basis for the distinction, question the underlying assumption that emotional harm is trivial, and contend that the distinction is anti-feminist, anti-communitarian, and overly formalistic. Accepting many of these insights as true, but noting where science, social science, and feminism actually support the distinction, this Article will contend that there are still descriptive differences between physical and emotional harm, as well as normative reasons to distinguish the two types of harm. Descriptively, courts and scholars have struggled to delineate precisely the definitions of physical and emotional harm, finding these categories obvious and ineffable. This Article constructs working definitions of bodily and emotional harm that require more exploration, but emotional distress”). Goldberg and Zipursky, while rejecting the notion that physical harms are categorically worse than emotional harms, establish a basis for distinguishing physical and emotional harms that relies on a narrative in which judges believe emotional health is, to a certain extent, within a plaintiff’s control. Id. at 1680–86. 24 Some view the duty question in torts as “a shorthand statement of a conclusion, rather than an aid to analysis in itself,” encompassing “considerations of policy which . . . say that the particular plaintiff is entitled to protection.” Dillon v. Legg, 441 P.2d 912, 916 (Cal. 1968) (citing PROSSER, LAW OF TORTS 332–33 (3d ed. 1964)). Whether the duty question retains its own logic within tort law or simply incorporates external public policy considerations, tort law should limit emotional duties we owe to others by expanding an emotional duty to take care of ourselves. 816 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 suffice for the purpose of defending the physical/emotional distinction. This Article will next justify the drawing, in tort law, of a distinction between physical and emotional harm. I argue that the physical/emotional hierarchy, or the ease of collecting on emotional injuries, should be based on conceptions of the types of duties we owe others, not on whether an injury can be measured objectively.25 The law should recognize for each of us a duty to reasonably regulate one’s own mental condition. An emotional duty of this type would foreclose or reduce damages recoverable in certain types of lawsuits for emotional distress, based on the instrumental and deontological perspectives embedded within law and economics, corrective justice, and civil recourse theories. There are many forms of laudable personal and social behavior that can produce unavoidable emotional harm as a byproduct. Duties to protect others from emotional harm should be limited not only to preserve spheres within which this laudable behavior can occur, but also to create a society where individuals seek help for mental disturbances, both before and after emotional distress. Neuroscience has begun to study the ways in which we can control our own minds, and scholars have explored how focusing on emotional harms as grievous wrongs tends to amplify them. Emphasizing the powerlessness of individuals over their emotional lives can diminish victims’ autonomy and can undermine notions of consent, especially for women. Ultimately, we are the keepers of our own minds and the law should reflect a morality where individuals cannot be compensated for harms over which they have relatively more control. The mental changes we undergo to cope with life are intimately connected to notions of free will and identity. Limiting defendants’ duties of protecting against emotional harm also maintains coherence with themes found in First Amendment law and criminal law. While appreciating the profound impact of emotional harm and de-stigmatizing mental illness, encouragement of mental fortitude can benefit potential plaintiffs and defendants. Finally, this Article will discuss the implications of maintaining the divide for tort doctrine. A new understanding of the physical/emotional distinction should center on the primacy of protection of the body and the recognition that individuals should assume greater responsibility for their own emotional health that is unrelated to bodily integrity. An emotional “reasonableness” requirement should be imposed on plaintiffs at the liability stage and the damages stage, both for stand-alone emotional distress and emotional injury that is parasitic on physical injury. However, the duty to take care of one’s emotional well-being is limited. When 25 Whether an injury can be proven objectively should be relevant to the issue of damages, not liability. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 817 emotional distress is so serious that it compromises our voluntary ability to exert emotional control, many of the reasons for maintaining the physical/emotional distinction disappear. Further, when emotional injury is bound up in either threats to bodily integrity or a violation of some other independent and significant interest, for which there is a separate duty, the breach of those duties may render irrelevant the victim’s duty of mental fortitude. Complicated questions arise when emotional injury leads to physical injury and vice versa, and this Article proposes ways to handle these issues consistent with a modern physical/emotional hierarchy. This Article will proceed in four parts. Part II will chart how tort law has treated the physical/emotional distinction. Part III will explore the criticisms of this distinction offered by neuroscience, social science, and feminist scholarship, but will also show how insights from these fields can support the distinction. Part IV will present a working definition of emotional injury, and will illustrate how this new conception of a duty to reasonably maintain one’s own emotional health, at the heart of the physical/emotional distinction, comports with tort theory’s instrumental and deontological values and echoes intuitions in other areas of the law. Part V will suggest doctrinal modifications to tort law in light of this recasting of the physical/emotional distinction. II. TORT LAW’S SELF-CONSCIOUS STRUGGLES WITH THE PHYSICAL/EMOTIONAL DISTINCTION In many areas of the law, courts cannot avoid confronting thorny questions concerning the categories of physical and emotional harm and the scope of the duties that we owe others to avoid causing them emotional harm.26 For example, when a car collides with a bike but the biker is not physically injured, is the driver responsible for the biker’s emotional distress stemming from the incident? What about the emotional distress of close relatives who witnessed the incident? Friends? A passersby? Does any or all of the analysis change if the biker is physically injured? In tort law, these confrontations have generated doctrine that perhaps embodies our intuitions,27 but which is especially rife with tortured rules and inconsistencies. Even as courts struggle with the physical/emotional distinction, there are echoes of unifying themes. Legal doctrine reflects a strong impulse to 26 For an exploration of how other areas of the law handle the physical/emotional distinction, see infra Part IV.B. 27 The physical/emotional divide deeply reflects our intuitions about what types of harm the law should prioritize. There is a reason that although there is “a growing trend to afford a privilege of selfdefense in connection with the use of physical force,” Rapp, supra note 7, at 110, we cannot use selfdefense to prevent the intentional infliction of emotional distress. This indicates that emotional wellbeing is not as valued in the law as physical safety. 818 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 separate physical and emotional injuries and it embodies the sense, sometimes only implicitly, that we have a greater duty to take steps to avoid causing others physical injury than emotional injury. Recognition of legal duties to avoid causing emotional distress is viewed as less problematic in special cases where individuals are in emotionally vulnerable situations or when an independent interest, separate from general emotional well-being, is involved. Courts now also seek ways to expand protection for emotional distress, in some cases by blurring the line between physical and emotional harm. A. The Tortured Path of Tort Law The life of tort law’s treatment of emotional harm seems to be neither logic nor experience.28 Judges, fearing the consequences of compensating emotional injury, while recognizing the serious impact of certain types of emotional distress, have attempted to limit claims for emotional harm in seemingly incoherent ways, drawing puzzling lines between compensable and non-compensable emotional injury.29 All jurisdictions now provide for compensation for some emotional injuries.30 The trend is toward continued liberalization of a plaintiff’s ability to collect on emotional claims.31 However, courts and the Second and Third Torts Restatements continue to maintain a categorical separation between physical and emotional harm,32 providing a general duty of care to avoid causing physical injuries but crafting only a “partial and fragmented patchwork of” duties for emotional 28 Holmes’ famous quote, “the life of the law is not logic but experience,” is a critique of legal formalism in favor of legal realism. Thomas C. Grey, Holmes and Legal Pragmatism, 41 STAN. L. REV. 787, 806 (1989). Tort law’s treatment of emotional harm, however, has attempted to draw bright, formalistic lines while evolving based on experience to incorporate growing sympathies towards plaintiffs who suffer emotional injury. 29 See, e.g., Camper v. Minor, 915 S.W.2d 437, 440 (Tenn. 1996) (describing the “inconsistency and incoherence in the law” of negligent infliction of emotional distress borne of trying to ferret out “the trivial or fraudulent claims that have been thought to be inevitable due to the subjective nature of [emotional] injuries”); Hunsley v. Giard, 553 P.2d 1096, 1098 (Wash. 1976) (en banc) (“Liability for negligently causing fright, mental disturbance, shock or emotional distress, resulting in physical injury, without impact to the person, has been a divided, confused and unsettled area of the law.”). The “impact rule,” for example, allows a plaintiff to collect emotional damages if he was touched by the slightest physical impact. Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1662–63. 30 See Edward Benedict Lumpkin, Note, Recovery of Emotional Distress Damages in AIDSPhobia Cases: A Suggested Approach for Virginia, 51 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 717, 718 (1994) (“[C]ourts in all jurisdictions overcame this fear of fraudulent claims and recognized an independent cause of action for emotional distress when the plaintiff meets certain threshold requirements. . . .”). 31 See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 4 cmt. d (2010) (“Since [the Second] Restatement, courts have liberalized the rules for recovery for stand-alone emotional harm.”). 32 See Consol. Rail Corp. v. Gottshall, 512 U.S. 532, 534 (1994) (adopting the “zone of danger test,” limiting recovery for emotional injury); see also RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 4 cmts. b, d (2010) (treating physical and emotional harm as separate categories). 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 819 33 injuries. Even though the Third Restatement notes the difficulty of clearly delineating between bodily harm and emotional harm,34 it preserves this distinction and stresses its importance.35 Initially, courts applying tort law were reluctant to compensate anything other than injury to the physical body or to personal property.36 The few torts that did not involve tangible harm, like assault or false imprisonment, were not conceptualized as recognizing claims for emotional distress. Rather, they were understood to protect and vindicate liberty interests—freedom from coercion by threat of physical harm and freedom from being physically confined against one’s will.37 The aversion to claims for emotional injury was based on a variety of concerns, most notably fear of fraudulent claims due to the subjective and unprovable nature of emotional injury,38 and reluctance to open the floodgates of litigation to the potentially limitless set of plaintiffs who could experience emotional suffering from any incident.39 Additionally, although not usually explicitly, courts seemed disinclined to create legal duties to avoid causing purely emotional harm, often based on either undervaluing emotional injury, or not wanting to cater to hypersensitivity.40 Starting in the early twentieth century, states somewhat liberalized 33 34 Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1670, 1673. RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 4 cmt. b (2010). 35 See id. (explaining that the distinction between bodily harm and emotional harm “is not precise and may be difficult to make in certain cases, but the more restrictive rules for recovery for emotional harm require that such determinations be made” (citation omitted)). 36 Levit, supra note 7, at 140 (“Historically, tort law compensated only direct and tangible injuries to persons or property.”). Levit explains that, “[t]he early history of tort law is not without examples of torts based on emotions, such as seduction or alienation of affections. But those torts were based on the possession of people as property interests.” Id. at 140 n.15; see also William R. Corbett, A Somewhat Modest Proposal to Prevent Adultery and Save Families: Two Old Torts Looking for a New Career, 33 ARIZ. ST. L.J. 985, 1025 (2001) (“Since the early twentieth century, there has been a movement in American tort law to loosen it from its moorings in recognizing recovery for only injury to physical person and property.”). 37 See Magruder, supra note 7, at 1035–36 (discussing the issue of separation of mental harm where the physical harm was an effect of the emotional distress). 38 See Chamallas, supra note 7, at 497 (“The popular cynicism surrounding the tort system may in part reflect the belief that plaintiffs who seek large sums for intangible injuries are the least deserving, that their very willingness to exploit the system is a testament to the superficiality of their injury.”). 39 See Leslie Benton Sandor & Carol Berry, Recovery for Negligent Infliction of Emotional Distress Attendant to Economic Loss: A Reassessment, 37 ARIZ. L. REV. 1247, 1253 (1995) (explaining that legal protections for emotional damages were considered in cases where bodily harm was caused as a result of nervous shock and emotional distress). 40 See Spade v. Lynn & B.R. Co., 47 N.E. 88, 89 (Mass. 1897) (explaining that asking people to “anticipate and guard against fright and the consequences of fright . . . would open a wide door for unjust claims”), overruled by Dziokonski v. Babineau, 380 N.E.2d 1295, 1299 (Mass. 1978); Lynch v. Knight, (1861) 11 Eng. Rep. 854 (H.L.C.) 863 (“Mental pain or anxiety the law cannot value, and does not pretend to redress . . . .”). 820 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 access to the courts for plaintiffs suffering from emotional injuries.41 To accomplish this, while remaining cognizant of the perils inherent in redressing emotional harm and attempting to preserve predictability in the doctrine, courts began to draw somewhat arbitrary lines between compensable and non-compensable emotional harm.42 Some courts began to treat certain types of emotional harm that could be objectively verified or had outward physical manifestations as bodily harm.43 The latest Restatement, however, rejects this approach, seeking to avoid “the unfortunate effect of diluting the definition of bodily harm.”44 In response to requests from law professors,45 and in recognition of feminist critiques of the physical/emotional distinction,46 courts and the Restatement have liberalized access to compensation for emotional injuries. Separate causes of action were created for the “stand alone” emotional harms of intentional infliction of emotional distress for behavior that was extreme and outrageous.47 Eventually, despite initial resistance,48 negligent infliction of emotional distress (NIED) also became a standard tort.49 The development of NIED has been a problematic process, and 41 Philip L. Merkel, Pain and Suffering Damages at Mid-Twentieth Century: A Retrospective View of the Problem and the Legal Academy’s First Responses, 34 CAP. U. L. REV. 545, 559 (2006). 42 See Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1671 (explaining that by the end of the twentieth century, courts drew lines restricting emotional distress claims without sound justification for making the distinctions). 43 See Reilly v. United States, 547 A.2d 894, 894–96 (R.I. 1988) (denying the emotional distress claims of parents who witnessed the negligent delivery of their child due to lack of outward manifestations of distress); Hunt v. Mercy Med. Ctr., 710 A.2d 362, 366 (Md. Ct. Spec. App. 1998) (“[A]n emotional injury (such as mental anguish or emotional distress) may come within the ambit of the ‘physical injury’ rule by virtue of its outward manifestations.”). 44 RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 4 cmt. d (2010). According to the Restatement, “emotional harm constituted physical illness,” which exists on the margin between physical and emotional injury, like headaches, nausea, or hysterical attacks, should be considered psychic injury. Id. 45 Rapp, supra note 7, at 113, 131–32; see also Merkel, supra note 41, at 555 (describing the legal academy’s efforts to advance a negligent infliction of emotional distress tort). 46 See Chamallas, supra note 7, at 525 (discussing the female experience of a physical harm becoming an emotional injury). 47 See, e.g., Miller v. Currie, 50 F.3d 373, 378 (6th Cir. 1995) (allowing an intentional infliction of emotional distress claim where a nursing home hid an elderly woman from her adult daughter and caused the daughter to be arrested for visiting her mother); Fletcher v. W. Nat’l Life Ins. Co., 89 Cal. Rptr. 78, 93, 99 (Cal. Ct. App. 1970) (finding that the defendant’s premeditated and malicious conduct of denying plaintiff disability benefits to save money was outrageous). 48 According to William Keaton, author of the Second Restatement, “[t]he temporary emotion of fright, so far from serious that it does no physical harm, is so evanescent a thing, so easily counterfeited, and usually so trivial, that the courts have been quite unwilling to protect the plaintiff against mere negligence, where the elements of extreme outrage and moral blame which have had such weight in the case of the intentional tort are lacking.” W. PAGE KEETON ET AL., PROSSER AND KEETON ON THE LAW OF TORTS 361 (5th ed. 1984) (citations omitted). 49 “The NIED tort represents the current wave of expansion and uncertainty in emotional distress liability.” Kontorovich, supra note 9, at 495. Only Arkansas and New Mexico prohibit any claims for 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 821 50 courts and scholars still struggle to make sense of this tort. At first, claims for negligently inflicted emotional distress required a plaintiff to allege and demonstrate some slight physical injury so that there was at least some de minimis physical impact or manifestation along with the emotional injury.51 Eventually, many courts adopted the zone of danger rule, which requires the plaintiff to prove having been distressed over the prospect of imminent physical harm by having been placed, by the defendant’s carelessness, in danger of such harm.52 These barriers to compensation for emotional injuries made little sense to most commentators,53 but courts preferred stand-alone emotional distress claims while mooring these claims to either some physical impact or risk of bodily harm. Although only a few states still maintain zone of danger requirements as a prerequisite for any NIED claim,54 all jurisdictions currently maintain some type of heightened pleading requirements for stand-alone emotional injury.55 The latest Restatement provides that intentional infliction of emotional distress is actionable if the defendant’s conduct is intentional/reckless and outrageous, and if it causes the plaintiff severe emotional injury.56 Negligent infliction of emotional distress is actionable negligent infliction of emotional distress. John J. Kircher, The Four Faces of Tort Law: Liability for Emotional Harm, 90 MARQ. L. REV. 789, 809 (2007); Rapp, supra note 7, at 138. 50 John C. P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Civil Recourse Defended: A Reply to Posner, Calabresi, Rustad, Chamallas, and Robinette, 88 IND. L.J. 569, 604 (2013) (“[I]ndeed we continue to wrestle with the topic of negligent infliction of emotional distress, as do many torts scholars of all political and methodological persuasions.”); Eugene Kontorovich, Comment, The Mitigation of Emotional Distress Damages, 68 U. CHI. L. REV. 491, 494 (2001) (“With negligent infliction of emotional distress torts . . . courts continue to struggle to create sensible limits on recovery while avoiding arbitrary limitations.”). 51 For excellent histories of the development of negligent infliction of emotional distress, see JOHN C. P. GOLDBERG ET AL., TORT LAW: RESPONSIBILITIES AND REDRESS 737–38, 753–59 (3d ed. 2012) (describing the development of claims for emotional distress in American tort law); Levit, supra note 7, at 141–44 (detailing the development of the tort over the course of the twentieth century, from the time that courts denied recovery for emotional injury alone to the recognition of mental disturbance as a cause of action). 52 RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 47 cmt. b (2012). 53 See, e.g., Levit, supra note 7, at 170–71 (“In using proxies such as ‘the zone of danger’ and the nature of the legal relationship between plaintiff and victim to test the reality and measure the severity of emotional injury, courts repair to awkward geographic indicators and formal status relationships as talismanic formulas to establish the existence of emotional harms. Yet the factors on which courts rely to confirm the presence of emotional distress often are not directly related to mental equilibrium.”). But see GOLDBERG ET AL., supra note 51, at 758 (explaining the zone of danger limitation as involving negligent endangerment that fortuitously did not result in physical injury). 54 David DePianto, The Hedonic Impact of “Stand-Alone” Emotional Harms: An Analysis of Survey Data, 36 LAW & PSYCHOL. REV. 115, 121–22 (2012). 55 See Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1673 n.131 (noting that two jurisdictions have “flirted with” a general duty to avoid emotional harm). 56 RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 46 (2012). 822 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 if it is serious and either (1) places the plaintiff at risk of physical harm, (2) occurs in the course of specified categories of activity or relationships where serious emotional harm is more likely to result,57 or (3) causes serious bodily harm to a close family member of the plaintiff, who contemporaneously perceives the harm.58 Further evidence of the Restatement’s liberalization of compensation for emotional damages appears in the rule that if an emotional injury leads to objectively measurable physical harm, such as a miscarriage or a suicide (but not merely nausea or headaches), then the plaintiff’s claim is one for physical injury, and the limited duty rules that would otherwise constrain liability no longer apply.59 This was not always the case, as miscarriages caused by fright were historically not compensable.60 Now, likely in response to feminist critiques, the Restatement allows emotional injury to serve as the conduit to claims of physical injury with its lower pleading requirements, but still maintains the categorical distinctions between physical and emotional injury. B. Parasitic Damages vs. The Eggshell Psyche Rule Although the development of torts for emotional injuries has been fractured, there are two doctrines on which courts generally agree— parasitic damages and the “eggshell psyche” rule. Parasitic damages involve damages for emotional distress or other injuries that flow from a physical injury.61 The “eggshell psyche” rule is a variant on the eggshell skull rule that would allow plaintiffs to collect for emotional damages even if their emotional response is unreasonable or the result of a pre-existing condition.62 Despite initial and some continued reluctance to compensate plaintiffs 57 Courts recognize relationships in which one party is particularly emotionally vulnerable due to the activities being performed by the other party. These include liability on hospitals and funeral homes for mishandling corpses and on telegraph companies who erroneously inform someone of the death of another. See id. at § 47 cmt. b (“[C]ourts have imposed liability on hospitals and funeral homes for negligently mishandling a corpse and on telegraph companies for negligently mistranscribing or misdirecting a telegram that informs the recipient, erroneously, about the death of a loved one.”). 58 Id. at § 48; cf. Appleton v. Bd. of Educ. of the Town of Stonington, 757 A.2d 1059 (Conn. 2000). 59 RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 4 cmt d (2012). 60 See Chamallas & Kerber, supra note 7, at 814–15 (arguing that miscarriages or stillbirths were one type of “fright-based physical injury” cases that the law did not recognize). 61 See, e.g., Norfolk & W. Ry. Co. v. Ayers, 538 U.S. 135, 148 (2003) (“Unlike stand-alone claims for negligently inflicted emotional distress, claims for pain and suffering associated with, or ‘parasitic’ on, a physical injury are traditionally compensable.”). 62 See, e.g., Gammon v. Osteopathic Hosp. of Me., Inc., 534 A.2d 1282, 1285 (Me. 1987) (“We do not provide compensation for the hurt feelings of the supersensitive plaintiff—the eggshell psyche.”). 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 823 for emotional injury, parasitic damage is one area where early courts uniformly allowed compensation for psychological harm.63 If a plaintiff demonstrates bodily injury or the invasion of certain other types of interests, he can be awarded the full extent of his psychological injuries without being subject to any heightened substantive standards, which are necessary when asserting purely emotional claims.64 Examples of damages given for pain and suffering “parasitic” to physical injury include emotional damage awards based on ingestion of tainted medication that causes physical injury,65 compensation for fear of developing cancer when the plaintiff suffered a physical injury leading to that fear,66 and damages for pain and suffering.67 These parasitic damages do not concern courts in the same way as stand-alone emotional claims, perhaps because courts are less concerned that parasitic emotional claims are fraudulent,68 or perhaps because parasitic damages do not threaten courts’ conception of physical injuries as more worthy of protection.69 Goldberg and Zipursky theorize that the disparate treatment of parasitic damages can be explained by the implicit view that emotional tranquility on its own, except in rare circumstances, is insufficient to saddle defendants with duties to protect others’ emotional well-being.70 Tort law is less willing to protect emotional injuries that are unrelated to either bodily integrity or to an independent, non-emotional 63 See Chamallas, supra note 7, at 491 (noting that courts justified awards for pain and suffering or other mental distress associated with physical injuries by explaining that the physical injury was the basis for the claim). 64 See, e.g., Gracey v. Eaker, 837 So. 2d 348, 350–51 (Fla. 2002) (holding that the impact rule, which requires that a plaintiff seeking emotional damages for negligence prove that her emotional injuries stemmed from a physical injury, was inapplicable in a case where the plaintiff also alleges a breach of fiduciary duty). 65 Hunter v. CVS Pharmacy, No. 1:09–CV–246, 2011 WL 167270, at *5 (E.D. Tenn. Jan. 19, 2011). 66 See, e.g., Ferrara v. Galluchio, 152 N.E.2d 249, 252–53 (N.Y. 1958) (upholding emotional distress damages where the plaintiff had been negligently burned in X-ray treatments and warned to have her tissue examined periodically to check for cancer). 67 Damages for “pain and suffering” can be for mental and physical pain. Kyle R. Crowe, The Semantical Bifurcation of Noneconomic Loss: Should Hedonic Damage Be Recognized Independently of Pain and Suffering Damage?, 75 IOWA L. REV. 1275, 1276 (1990). 68 Flax v. Daimlerchrysler Corp., 272 S.W.3d 521, 527 (Tenn. 2008) (noting that parasitic damages “avoid[] the trivial or fraudulent claims that have been thought to be inevitable due to the subjective nature of [emotional] injuries.” (quoting Camper v. Minor, 915 S.W.2d 437, 440 (Tenn. 1996))). 69 According to Martha Chamallas, “[w]hen plaintiffs recovered for pain and suffering or other mental distress associated with physical injuries, the courts were careful to explain that these damages were ‘parasitic’ and that the cause of action was fundamentally based on physical injury.” Chamallas, supra note 7, at 491. 70 See Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1673 (“[A]ctors are not ordinarily under a legal duty to be vigilant of others’ emotional well-being.”). 824 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 71 interest. This reasoning underlies why torts like slander and libel have a long history of compensability, even though these torts are often accompanied by, and perhaps primarily manifested through, emotional distress.72 Even so, emotional distress does not form the injury giving rise to claims for defamation: “there is still a predicate harm in this case—the intangible predicate harm of reputational damage—that provides the foundation for the cause of action.”73 Courts thus allow emotional distress claims parasitic on an independent tort without the heightened showing necessary for stand-alone emotional distress.74 However, in many cases, even where there is some other interest at stake—like the freedom from physical injury or property damage caused by a defective product in products liability law,75 or the interest in the quiet enjoyment of one’s property in nuisance law76—courts still refuse to compensate plaintiffs who have experienced only emotional injuries. If a plaintiff’s defective lawnmower explodes without endangering him physically, yet he is nonetheless seriously distressed, then that distress alone is not compensable. These areas of tort law demonstrate courts’ continuing desire to distinguish physical from emotional harms. Like parasitic damages, the courts have generally handled “unreasonable” emotional reactions uniformly. Most courts bar recovery for stand-alone emotional injury, like negligent infliction of emotional distress, unless a defendant’s actions are of a sort that would cause serious emotional distress, even to a person of reasonable or ordinary resilience.77 This is a deviation from the treatment of physical harm in two ways. First, to recover for physical injury, there is no requirement that a 71 Id. at 1668. Id. at 1689. 73 Id. 74 See, e.g., Jacobsen v. Allstate Ins. Co., 215 P.3d 649, 649 (Mont. 1999) (holding that a plaintiff need not satisfy the heightened threshold showing of serious or severe emotional injury for emotional damages that are parasitic on an Unfair Trade Practices Act claim against auto insurer). 75 RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: PRODS. LIAB. § 21 (1998). 76 Gregory C. Keating, Nuisance as a Strict Liability Wrong, 4 J. TORT L. 1, 23 (2012) (“[P]ure emotional harm such as fears arising from the perception of an environmental risk, or the perceived undesirability of certain neighbors, will generally not suffice to make out a claim of nuisance.”). 77 See, e.g., Theriault v. Swan, 558 A.2d 369, 372 (Me. 1989) (“In order to recover for either negligent or reckless infliction of emotional distress, a plaintiff must demonstrate that the harm alleged reasonably could have been expected to befall the ordinarily sensitive person.”); RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 47 cmt. j (2012) (“The requirements that the harm be serious, that the circumstances of the case be such that a reasonable person would suffer serious harm, and that there be credible evidence that the plaintiff has suffered such harm better serve the purpose of screening claims than a requirement of physical consequences.”). 72 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 825 78 plaintiff’s physical harm be serious. Second, under the “eggshell plaintiff” rule that applies to physical injury, a defendant is liable for the full extent of a plaintiff’s physical harm, even if that physical harm resulted from the plaintiff’s being easily injured or having a preexisting condition that renders him physically infirm.79 For example, a defendant was liable to the decedent of a plaintiff who suffered from coronary disease after a car accident, which caused him to suffer bruised ribs and a fractured ankle, resulted in a heart attack days later.80 In the case of stand-alone emotional injury, for a defendant to be liable at all, the emotional injury needs to be not only serious, but also of a sort that would have been suffered by a person of ordinary resilience.81 In such a case, a plaintiff can recover the full extent of his emotional damages, even above and beyond those that a reasonable person would have suffered.82 In this way, a modified “eggshell psyche” rule attaches at the phase of determining the extent of damages, which will be fully awarded if an injury is reasonably serious. That all physical injuries, regardless of how trivial or unreasonable, subject defendants to liability to their full extent is another indicator that bodily integrity is deemed more protectable than emotional tranquility. III. CHALLENGES TO THE PHYSICAL/EMOTIONAL DISTINCTION For almost a century, scholars have questioned the lesser protection that tort law affords emotional injuries.83 In recent years, scientific advances and critical examinations of the distinction have eroded our intuitions about the differences between physical and emotional harms. New developments in neuroscience and social science have provided 78 See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 4 cmt. c (2010) (“Given the function of the definition, any level of physical impairment is sufficient for liability; no minimum amount of physical harm is required.”). 79 See Levit, supra note 7, at 178–79 (“Tort plaintiffs with ‘eggshell’ skulls are recompensed for all resulting injuries, while those with ‘eggshell’ psyches are denied any compensation.” (footnotes omitted)). 80 Benn v. Thomas, 512 N.W.2d 537, 538 (Iowa 1994). 81 See Rodrigues v. State, 472 P.2d 509, 520 (Haw. 1970) (defining a serious or severe injury as one “where a reasonable person, normally constituted, would be unable to adequately cope with the mental stress engendered by the circumstances of the case”). 82 In most jurisdictions courts ask would a reasonable plaintiff suffer serious emotional distress, but once this is established, the extent of damages does not depend on the reasonable person. See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 47 cmt. l (2010). 83 See Francis H. Bohlen, Fifty Years of Torts, 50 HARV. L. REV. 725, 732–34 (1937) (discussing how courts tend to limit or deny recovery for emotional harms); Richard Delgado, Words That Wound; A Tort Action for Racial Insults, Epithets, and Name Calling, 17 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 133, 143–45 (1982) (stating that it is an affront to the American tradition against stigmatization that the emotional harm caused by racial slurs is not recognized as a dignity harm); Magruder, supra note 7, at 1042–43 (stating that many courts will allow emotional harm only if the plaintiff also suffered some sort of physical harm). 826 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 information bearing on the normative justifications for the physical/emotional distinction.84 Feminist scholars have challenged these normative justifications head on, arguing that the distinction both reflects and perpetuates gender bias.85 These criticisms, taken together, convincingly refute certain standard justifications for the distinction between physical and emotional harm. While one conclusion to draw from such a refutation would be to discard the distinction, it is not the only possible conclusion. I argue instead that these critiques augment our understanding of emotional harm and provide a more compelling justification for the distinction. Further, support for the mental/physical distinction can be found within neuroscience, social science, and feminist scholarship. A. Measuring Emotional Harm One pillar of the physical/emotional distinction is the insistence that only physical harms can be directly observed and verified.86 If emotional harm could be objectively detected and measured, there would be less concern that plaintiffs will fake emotional injuries, and less reason to afford emotional harm inferior status. Although technology does not provide us with the capacity to conclusively demonstrate the existence or severity of psychic injuries, a sustainable justification for the physical/emotional hierarchy must confront technology’s increasing capacity to do so. Technology that measures activity in the brain has improved at a dramatic rate,87 and, with it, neuroscientists’ understanding of the regulation of emotions has also improved. By the early twentieth century, medical doctors and psychologists had amassed research that emotional disturbances affect individuals on a physiological level.88 Scientists can now use functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) to measure the 84 See Adam J. Kolber, The Experiential Future of the Law, 60 EMORY L.J. 585, 587–88 (2011) (“[T]echnological advances in neuroscience are beginning to provide more accurate methods of measuring experiences.”). 85 See Cordelia Fine, Is There Neurosexism in Functional Neuroimaging Investigations of Sex Differences?, 6 NEUROETHICS 369, 370 (2013) (noting that feminists are challenging current neuroimaging studies for perpetuating traditional gender biases). 86 R. Bruner, Proving Emotional Harm in Tort Law, NEULAW (Nov. 30, 1999), http:neulaw.org/blog/1034-class-biol/2346-proving-emotional-harm-in-tort-law. 87 See Kolber, supra note 84, at 588. 88 Nockleby & Curreri, supra note 7, at 1071; see, e.g., Herbert F. Goodrich, Emotional Disturbance as Legal Damage, 20 MICH. L. REV. 497, 498 (1922) (explaining that Drs. George W. Crile and Walter B. Cannon’s research established strong links between emotions and physical aspects of the body); Fowler V. Harper & Mary Coate McNeely, A Re-examination of the Basis for Liability for Emotional Distress, 1938 WIS. L. REV. 426, 426 (“It is true, of course, that all emotional disturbances are at the same time physiological so that the distinction between emotional distress and physical harm, as usually drawn by the courts, may not be strictly scientific.”). 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 827 89 effects of certain types of psychological harm. The fMRI technique measures blood flow throughout the brain.90 The theory behind fMRI is that localized areas of the brain that are active, for example in response to a painful stimulus, require more oxygen.91 This increased oxygen consumption creates an increased flow of oxygenated blood to serve active neurons.92 An fMRI machine measures the increased flow of blood using a signal called the Blood Oxygen Level Dependent (BOLD) signal.93 Other tools measure brain activity besides fMRI. A positron emission tomography (PET) scan uses decaying radioactive isotopes to detect energy metabolism, which is linked to brain function,94 much as fMRI uses the BOLD signal to detect blood flow. Scientists can now use fMRI and PET scans to study the types of “invisible injuries” that are normally considered non-physical, like pain and emotional distress.95 Already, fMRI scans have been used to differentiate patients with chronic pain from those without pain.96 Studies indicate that an individual’s self-reported degree of pain correlates fairly well with activation of the regions of the brain that mediate pain.97 In subjects who are uncoached, those merely imagining the idea of pain can be distinguished on an fMRI scan from those actually experiencing pain.98 Functional brain scanning technology is also beginning to have the capacity to objectively measure and demonstrate the changes in neural 89 In addition to fMRI, there are many other techniques for mapping the brain’s structure and function, such as electroencephalography and scans using positron emission technology, but fMRI is believed to have the most potential for furthering our understanding of the brain and behavior. See Laurence R. Tancredi & Jonathan D. Brodie, The Brain and Behavior: Limitations in the Legal Use of Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging, 33 AM. J.L. & MED. 271, 271–72 (2007) (discussing how fMRI can be used to study the effect of emotional harm on the brain). 90 Shaun Cassin, Comment, Eggshell Minds and Invisible Injuries: Can Neuroscience Challenge Longstanding Treatment of Tort Injuries, 50 HOUS. L. REV. 929, 941 (2013) (quoting Owen D. Jones et al., Brain Imaging for Legal Thinkers: A Guide for the Perplexed, 2009 STAN. TECH. L. REV. 5, ¶ 17). 91 Id. 92 Tancredi & Brodie, supra note 89, at 274–75. 93 Id. For a thorough discussion of the significance of the BOLD signal in determining which neurons are actually firing, see Teneille Brown & Emily Murphy, Through a Scanner Darkly: Functional Neuroimaging as Evidence of a Criminal Defendant’s Past Mental States, 62 STAN. L. REV. 1119, 1139–40 (2010). 94 Cassin, supra note 90, at 942; Tancredi & Brodie, supra note 89, at 274, 276–77. 95 See Cassin, supra note 90, at 942–43 (stating that fMRI and PET can be used for plaintiffs to prove their emotional or invisible injuries). 96 See M. C. Lee & I. Tracey, Imaging Pain: A Potent Means for Investigating Pain Mechanisms in Patients, 111 BRIT. J. ANAESTHESIA 64, 67 (2013), available at http://bja.oxfordjournals.org/ content/111/1/64.full.pdf+html (“Early fMRI studies have shown altered functional activation for PFC by noxious stimuli in patients with chronic pain.”). 97 Amanda C. Pustilnik, Pain as Fact and Heuristic: How Pain Neuroimaging Illuminates Moral Dimensions of Law, 97 CORNELL L. REV. 801, 812 (2012). 98 Stuart W.G. Derbyshire et al., Cerebral Activation During Hypnotically Induced and Imagined Pain, 23 NEUROIMAGE 392, 395, 398 (2004). 828 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 99 circuitry that accompany serious emotional harm. Grey: According to Betsy Extensive and replicated research has revealed brain regions that are associated with emotional trauma. In particular, structural and functional neuroimaging results implicate specific subregions of the medial prefrontal cortex (MPFC), orbitofrontal cortex (OFC), anterior cingulated (ACC), and insular cortices, the amygdala, and the hippocampus in the processing of emotional information. Research suggests that dysfunction in this circuitry triggers and maintains emotional disorders.100 One of the most commonly studied instances of emotional trauma evidenced by disruption to neural pathways is Post Traumatic Stress Disorder (PTSD). This disorder occurs after an individual consolidates the memory of a traumatic event.101 When an individual is subjected to extreme stress, the amygdala, which serves as the emotion center and stimulates arousal, becomes hyperactive.102 At the same time, the prefrontal cortex, which allows the individual to process and understand those emotions, becomes less active.103 This leads an individual with an acute anxiety disorder, such as PTSD, to display a threat-oriented bias in interpreting events.104 Using fMRI and PET scans, scientists have examined the dysregulation of the amygdala and pre-frontal cortex in patients suffering from PTSD.105 The delayed emotional effects of exposure to a traumatic event, and even emotional changes based on brief exposures to a single stressor, can now be objectively measured.106 In light of science’s increasing ability to measure emotional harm, scholars argue that continued dedication to the rigid categories of physical and emotional harm reflects backward, unscientific thinking.107 Betsy 99 But see Cassin, supra note 90, at 959 (“In the near future, neuroscience will likely be a helpful tool for litigants with invisible injuries. In contrast, it will not be useful for plaintiffs with emotional injuries.”). 100 Grey, Neuroscience and Emotional Harm in Tort Law, supra note 7, at 213 and accompanying notes. 101 Id. at 213–15. 102 Id. at 214–15. 103 Id. at 214–15. 104 Id. at 215. 105 Lisa M. Shin et al., Regional Cerebral Blood Flow in the Amygdala and Medial Prefrontal Cortex During Traumatic Imagery in Male and Female Vietnam Veterans with PTSD, 61 ARCHIVES GEN. PSYCHIATRY 168–69 (2004). 106 See Grey, Neuroscience and Emotional Harm in Tort Law, supra note 7, at 217–18 (compiling studies). 107 For example, in response to the proposed Restatement (Third) of Torts, with its “relentless emphasis” on the distinction between physical and emotional harm, Oscar Grey commented that “[a]t a minimum, this ‘emotional’/‛physical’ distinction casts a pall of apparent antiscience over our work and 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 829 Grey, for example, argues that “this may be an appropriate time to reexamine our assumptions with regard to tort recovery for emotional harm.”108 She proposes that the American system of evaluating emotional distress should conform to the English approach.109 The English “unitary view” abolishes the distinction between physical and emotional harm and treats emotional harm “as an aspect of bodily harm”110 if the plaintiff can show a diagnosable psychiatric illness.111 But neuroscience has its shortcomings, both practically and philosophically, in undermining the physical/emotional distinction. Scholars and scientists who argue that emotional injuries are the same as physical injuries in their ability to be demonstrated objectively overstate their case. The use of fMRI currently has many scientific limitations, and it is expensive to administer.112 Further, this technology is vulnerable to the malingering that impacts the way fMRI results appear because “we have some control over our own brain activity.”113 Measuring emotional distress presents even more challenges than other uses of fMRI. Each brain is highly individualized, so it is difficult to determine what a “normal” brain looks like and thus whether the plaintiff’s brain is functioning abnormally.114 Additionally, subjects usually do not have baseline scans to reveal whether their brains have been altered after a distressing event, presenting major problems for causation. However, technology that can render emotional injuries more objective is improving rapidly. It may be true that “[e]merging technologies will enable us to make inferences about others’ experiences more frequently and with greater precision.”115 At least one court has already determined that objective proof of the physiological basis for emotional injuries can erase the distinction between bodily and emotional harm. In Allen v. Bloomfield Hills School District,116 the plaintiff, a train conductor, suffered from PTSD after colliding with an empty bus that he thought was filled with schoolchildren.117 A Michigan appellate court held that the plaintiff’s psychological injuries could constitute a bodily injury, given a doctor’s affidavit that a PET scan “depicted decreases in frontal and subcortical makes us appear obsolete from the outset.” Gray, Negligent Infliction of Emotional Distress, supra note 7, at 1193. 108 Grey, Neuroscience and Emotional Harm in Tort Law, supra note 7, at 203. 109 Id. at 204–05. 110 Id. 111 Id. at 220. 112 See id. at 278–286 (discussing the difficulties in using fMRI to measure brain function). 113 Kolber, supra note 84, at 600. 114 Cassin, supra note 90, at 945. 115 Kolber, supra note 84, at 589. 116 760 N.W.2d 811 (Mich. Ct. App. 2008). 117 Id. at 817–18 (Hoekstra, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). 830 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 activity consistent with depression and post traumatic stress disorder.”118 According to the court, “there should be no difference medically or legally between an objectively demonstrated brain injury, whether the medical diagnosis is a closed head injury, PTSD, . . . etc.”119 The Michigan court’s treatment of emotional harm as bodily injury is ultimately unsustainable. The court created a legal category of “bodily harm” that seems driven by prudential concerns about whether an injury can be proven. This sort of line, between injuries that are currently measurable and those that are not, has some appeal, but would subject the duties we owe others to scientific constraints and progress. It would undermine tort law’s expression of our normative social values and ability to shape behavior based on accumulated notions of what we owe others versus what we preserve in spheres of personal autonomy.120 Tort law embeds normative ideals about what harms are protectable, and therefore the line between protectable and un-protectable harm should not be determined by the latest trends in scientific research. Beyond that, developments in neuroscience can actually bolster the argument for placing on victims at least some responsibility for handling their emotional responses to traumatic events. In addition to demonstrating that emotional injuries have objective, measurable components, neuroscience is also revealing that individuals have the ability to affect their own emotional states and even their own perception of pain. Studies are beginning to show how much we can control our own brains. Scientists have demonstrated how we can improve our memory and cognitive functioning by performing certain tasks,121 and now neuroscience is tackling our ability to control the parts of our brain that regulate pain and emotion. As examples, training subjects to regulate the activation of the rostral anterior, a brain region involved in pain regulation, causes a change in the perception of a noxious stimulus.122 Teaching subjects to increase activation in the anterior insula, involved in a variety of functions relevant 118 Id. at 814–15 (internal quotation marks omitted). Id. at 816. 120 This statement about the functions of tort law holds true whether one “demand[s] a persuasive normative theory of the function or value of tort law prior to engaging in first-order tort theorizing” or whether one looks at the normative structure of tort law internally, by “exploring the connections among the normative concepts and principles of tort law and ascertaining how they fit together within the law.” Benjamin C. Zipursky, Rawls in Tort Theory: Themes and Counter-themes, 72 FORDHAM L. REV. 1923, 1936–37 (2004). In either case, tort law serves purposes that either are, or should be, manifest in the doctrine. 121 See, e.g., Eleanor A. Maguire et al., London Taxi Drivers and Bus Drivers: A Structural MRI and Neuropsychological Analysis, 16 HIPPOCAMPUS 1091, 1094–1101 (2006) (explaining how taxi drivers improved their memory when compared to bus drivers). 122 R. Christopher deCharms et al., Control over Brain Activation and Pain Learned by Using Real-Time Functional MRI, 102 PROCEEDINGS NAT’L ACAD. SCI. U.S. 18626, 18627 (2005). 119 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 831 123 to emotion, causes them to rate photographs more negatively. These studies involve subjects who are taught to regulate their own emotions by activating certain parts of their brain, but they indicate that individuals have the ability to temper their own perception of emotions and pain. In addition to fMRI studies, psychological studies also indicate that low mood states and conditions, like major clinical depression, can be alleviated using a variety of self-help techniques, like self-acceptance.124 Emotions may be as “real” physiologically as physical responses are, but if they are more within our control, then the law ought to continue distinguishing between them, at least to some extent.125 B. Valuing Emotional Harm Not only does research indicate that emotional harms are rooted in and detected by physiological changes, but social science is demonstrating that emotional injuries, like sadness, hurt, loss, or mental health issues, are often as damaging as physical harms. These findings refute the argument underlying some courts’ efforts to maintain the physical/emotional distinction that emotional harms are trivial when compared to physical harms. Cass Sunstein, for example, examined social science research on hedonic value to conclude that individuals often overestimate the hedonic losses from physical injuries.126 Even the loss of fingers and toes pose little permanent hedonic damage because “human beings are unexpectedly resilient,”127 as compared to the enduring hedonic losses of mental illness or chronic pain.128 Sunstein proposes a line separating compensable, enduring injuries and noncompensable, illusory losses to which people quickly adapt.129 A distinction between enduring and illusory harm would cut across the physical/emotional distinction and thus, in principle, sometimes support expanding liability for wrongful conduct causing 123 Andrea Caria et al., Volitional Control of Anterior Insula Activity Modulates the Response to Aversive Stimuli, 68 BIOLOGICAL PSYCHIATRY 425, 425 (2010). 124 Alice Diedrich et al., Self-Compassion as an Emotion Regulation Strategy in Major Depressive Disorder, 58 BEHAV. RES. & THERAPY, July 2014, at 44. 125 Fox & Stein, supra note 5, at 16. Fox and Stein argue that plaintiffs have no greater ability to control emotional harms than physical harms. Id. This conclusion appears to be based only on the interdependence of functions of the mind and functions of the body. See id. at 7 (describing the concept of “mind-body dualism”). However, the fact that the same “laws of physics” control both the brain and the body, and that emotional injuries may cause physical symptoms and vice versa, does not rebut the argument that emotional injuries that arise in the mind may be experienced and regulated differently than other somatic injuries. Id. at 6. 126 Sunstein, supra note 14, at S164–66. Sunstein uses the term “hedonic” to capture the emerging literature of how certain events impact the enjoyment of one’s life. Id. at S160. 127 Id. at S164. 128 Id. at S167. 129 Id. at S158. 832 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 130 emotional distress. Building on Sunstein’s article, David DePianto challenges the view that stand-alone emotional harms are “everyday, usually trivial, often transient, and a part of the price of living among people.”131 DePianto performed empirical research on subjective well-being, an indicator of happiness, to demonstrate that emotional health exerts a strong impact on happiness, often stronger than physical health.132 Using data from over 55,000 participants,133 DePianto created regression models with, as a dependent variable, questions asking participants to rate their happiness and, as the independent variable, answers to a variety of questions about the mental and physical health of the participants.134 He found that the connection between emotional health and subjective well-being has even stronger statistical significance than the correlation between physical health and subjective well-being.135 Further, there is a strong correlation between subjective well-being and emotional/mental health even in individuals experiencing no physical infirmities.136 This finding refutes the claim that physical injury contributes to emotional distress in cases where emotional health is strongly correlated with subjective well-being.137 DePianto’s study illustrates the enormous impact of mental and emotional health on happiness, even in comparison to physical health. DePianto’s findings “challenge the distinctions currently drawn in tort law” but only “[t]o the extent that the unequal treatment of physical and emotional harms is based not upon practical concerns but upon the belief that mental health is less important to the quality of life . . . .”138 Subjective 130 See id. (“It is important for the legal system to distinguish between harms that impose enduring losses, such as chronic pain and mental illness, and harms that do not, such as losses of fingers and toes.”). This distinction accords with Joel Feinberg’s widely known distinction between harm and offense. See generally JOEL FEINBERG, HARM TO OTHERS 26 (1984) (distinguishing between the “Harm Principle” and the “Offense Principle”). Feinberg traces the moral justifications for criminally outlawing behavior by first demonstrating that the criminal law can intervene to prevent harm, or wrongful setbacks to interest. Id. at 31–64. Feinberg then illustrates that the law can intervene to prevent offense, or temporarily unpleasant mental states, but under more limited circumstances. Id. at 126–186. Like Sunstein, Feinberg’s line between harm and offense does not track the physical/emotional distinction—disruption to emotional tranquility that sets back an interest is considered a harm—but between longer lasting injury and fleeting unpleasantness. 131 DePianto, supra note 54, at 123 (footnotes omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted). 132 Id. at 115, 118. 133 Id. at 132–33. 134 Id. at 133–34. For example, one of the mental health questions asked to participants was, “[d]uring the past 4 weeks, have you had any of the following problems with your work or other daily activities as a result of any emotional problems (such as feeling depressed or anxious)?” Id. at 133. 135 Id. at 137. 136 Id. at 137, 141. 137 See id. at 122–23 (discussing the devaluation of emotional distress in the absence of physical injuries). 138 Id. at 141. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 833 well-being studies have limitations and vocal critics, and even DePianto admits that relating emotional health to happiness may be question begging, as people may define happiness based on their emotional wellbeing.139 DePianto adequately answers this objection by showing how the questions about emotional health and stability are sufficiently specific to distinguish them from general notions of happiness.140 This Article accepts the wisdom that emotional harm is often as impactful as physical harm. For every quantum of physical harm less extreme than death, there may be a matching emotional injury. Momentary embarrassment or hurt may be trivial, but so is a scratch. A complete and permanent psychological breakdown can be as debilitating as paralysis. People might rather be punched in the face than lose their jobs, or break an arm rather than have their heart broken. Often our emotional health dictates our happiness and productivity far more than our physical capacities. There is no reason to think that an enduring emotional injury is no more impactful than an enduring physical injury, even if many emotional injuries are more fleeting than many physical injuries. The idea that emotional harm is trivial stems from a time when mental illness was stigmatized, and, perhaps, when women’s voices and experiences were not equally represented in consciousness shaping and judicial decision-making.141 Indeed, some might go even further, and argue that the way our mind experiences the world is the only thing that matters, and that emotional well-being is therefore paramount. We may be in physical decay, but if our mind remains happy and cannot appreciate the pain, then our experience is still of a good life. To this, J. J. C. Smart presents Robert Nozick’s famous “experience machine” hypothetical: Suppose there were an experience machine that would give you any experience you desired. Superduper neuropsychologists could stimulate your brain so that you would think and feel you were writing a great novel, or making a friend, or reading an interesting book. All the time you would be floating in a tank, with electrodes attached to your brain. Should you plug into this machine for life, preprogramming your life’s experiences?142 For those of us who would not plug into the machine, internal states of happiness, fulfillment, and perception are less important than the truth of 139 Id. at 118. See id. at 133–37 (discussing and evaluating the different variables used in questioning). 141 See infra Part III.C (describing the under-protection of emotional distress in tort law because of its connection with women). 142 See J. J. C. Smart, An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics, in UTILITARIANISM: FOR AND AGAINST 3, 42 (J. J. C. Smart & Bernard Williams eds., 1973). 140 834 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 the tangible connections with the outside world. Adam Kolber, who argues that the law should more highly value subjective experience, believes that the results indicating that most people would not plug into the machine are partially due to a “status quo” bias; people choose their current situation over a new situation, even when the new situation is an improvement.143 Research that attempts to reverse this status quo bias found that, when told to imagine that their current lives were just the experience machine, fiftyfour percent of subjects would chance reality in a neutral scenario, but only thirteen percent of subjects would disconnect from the machine if reality were to be lived out as a prisoner in a maximum security facility.144 Although this study indicates that subjective experience can outweigh the importance of “reality,” our brain’s perceptions of that experience are not all that matter. It is still the descriptions of what life would be like on or off the machine that determine whether the individual would remain connected to the machine, not a conclusion that a person is happy or miserable. The inputswhat we put into the experience machine, be it a vacation, a family, or a jobmatter to people, not just the final feeling states of happiness, sadness, and so on. People are attuned to what makes them feel particular things, not just the feelings themselves. The law should prioritize these inputs, the physical connections between people and tangible changes in the outside world that create our subjective experiences and feelings, not the feelings themselves. Our brains may simply be experience machines that react to all we perceive and effectuate, but the law has much less of a place navigating our internal emotional lives than it does controlling the physical interactions that serve as inputs into the machine. If the law seeks to protect particular interests, like a reputational interest, an interest in bodily integrity, or an interest in non-discrimination, it should protect these interests directly. It can allow damages for emotional distress that flow from these infringements,145 instead of allowing the province of the mind to be an end in and of itself. The law should prioritize individual’s rights and interests instead of forcing people to take responsibility for others’ emotional states. C. Gendering Emotional Harm Criticisms based on neuroscience and social science remove some of the justifications for the physical/emotional hierarchy, but leave room for other rationales to maintain the distinction. The feminist critique instead attacks the physical/emotional construct as stemming from bias and 143 144 Kolber, supra note 84, at 593. Felipe De Brigard, If You like It, Does It Matter If It’s Real?, 23 PHIL. PSYCHOL. 43, 47–48 (2010). 145 See infra Part IV (describing doctrinal suggestions along these lines). 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 835 perpetuating bias. Ultimately, however, even if the categories of physical and emotional harm have roots in sexism, and even if these categories continue to have a disparate impact on women, the physical/emotional distinction could still be justified by other, legitimate rationales. In fact, maintaining the physical/emotional hierarchy may even promote women’s equality and autonomy. Feminist scholars argue that emotional harm has been under-protected in tort law because emotional distress is a concern mostly relevant to women.146 Martha Chamallas likens the treatment of emotional distress claims to the lower wages paid by jobs primarily associated with females; both emotional injury and primarily female occupations are considered of lesser status because of this association.147 Studies of wage gaps between men and women who hold jobs of comparable worth, conducted both in the United States and cross-culturally,148 have shown that pay or prestige drops when a particular job becomes female-dominated.149 This example of the wage gap, however, cannot bear the load of proving that emotional injuries are devalued because of their association with women.150 The claim that female-dominated jobs receive less compensation because women’s work is devalued is itself a controversial descriptive account. Because “worth” is such a subjective term, “it is scarcely surprising that different evaluators and evaluation systems have attached different values to identical positions,”151 undermining the claim that women receive lower pay in jobs of “comparable worth” to maledominated fields. Chamallas herself points to a study demonstrating that women enter certain fields due to their lower status, earning potential, and subsequent “male flight.”152 Thus, the cause and effect may be reversed; a 146 See Chamallas, supra note 7, at 499 (“[L]egal claims for emotional distress have been devalued in part because they are associated with female plaintiffs.”); Chamallas & Kerber, supra note 7, at 816 (arguing that the reluctance to accept negligent infliction of emotional distress is partially due to the marginalization of women and their experiences). 147 Chamallas, supra note 7, at 474–80. 148 Id. at 475–77 (citing ALICE H. COOK, COMPARABLE WORTH: THE PROBLEM AND THE STATES’ APPROACHES TO WAGE EQUITY 80–81 (1983)). 149 In Russia, where a large majority of doctors are women, the position has much less status and prestige than in America. Chamallas, supra note 7, at 477, 477 n.41. 150 Chamallas’ own empirical research also convincingly demonstrates that women receive lower damages awards generally, see id. at 480–82 (discussing a finding of lower damage awards to women based on their lower work-life expectancy when compared to caucasian men), but this does not speak to whether the physical/emotional distinction embodies and perpetuates deep cultural biases. Chamallas contends that the fact that statistical tables select gender and race as predictors of lifetime earning capacity is based on cognitive biases and gender- and race-based devaluation. Id. at 482–83. However, these tables also use age, likely because all of these variables offer some population-based correlation to income. 151 Deborah L. Rhode, Occupational Inequality, 1988 DUKE L.J. 1207, 1230. 152 See Chamallas, supra note 7, at 477 (citing BARBARA F. RESKIN & PATRICIA A. ROOS, JOB QUEUES, GENDER QUEUES: EXPLAINING WOMEN’S INROADS INTO MALE OCCUPATIONS 11–15 (1990)) 836 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 field may become female dominated because it is devalued, not the other way around. Just as the causal connection remains unclear in the wage gap examples, it is possible that emotional damages are associated with women and devalued, for either legitimate or illegitimate reasons, without an underlying causal connection between the two. Chamallas and Kerber also make a compelling case that the law of fright historically limited recovery for women who suffered miscarriages after experiencing nervous shock or witnessing physical harm to their children because men did not experience comparable harm.153 However, judges today do not seem to be operating on the same biases that women’s interests are less worthy of concern, or that women’s emotional frailty is less compensable.154 It is possible, as Chamallas proposes, that a “conceptual vicious cycle” unconsciously perpetuates historical sexism by classifying harm that could be either physical or emotional as emotional if it is associated with women.155 However, even if part of the reason why emotional damages are considered worthy of lesser protection, either historically or currently, is their association with women, there still may be other, more significant reasons for maintaining the physical/emotional hierarchy. The hierarchy that values physical harm over emotional harm may have a disparate impact on women, who are generally the caregivers of children and the most emotionally affected by their losses,156 and who are also generally the victims of sexual harassment, a tort circumscribed because it is primarily emotional in nature.157 But, as Chamallas acknowledges, disparate impact is an insufficient justification in itself to eliminate a legal category. Legitimate rules, which foster worthy social aims, can have a disparate impact on either gender. Chamallas’ concern must be that these categories perpetuate biases for no good reason. According to Chamallas, because “the basic categories of physical injury, property damage, emotional harm, and relational harm are themselves (arguing that women entered clerical jobs vacated by men once the fields began to deteriorate due to factors such as decreased wages and mobility). 153 Chamallas & Kerber, supra note 7, at 814. 154 Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1669. 155 Chamallas, supra note 7, at 469. She uses the example of miscarriages resulting from emotional distress, which courts historically treated as emotional injury. Id. at 525. Her account may be correct, but it is also plausible that courts were reluctant to categorize as “physical” subsequent injury that was caused by the emotional effects of malfeasance, not by the malfeasance itself. Focusing on the mechanism of the injury harmonizes consideration of miscarriages with intervening actor doctrines, where the woman’s own distress intervened to convert an emotional injury into a physical injury. The Restatement currently treats bodily injury that results from emotional distress as actionable bodily injury if it is objectively measurable, but not if it produces vague, immeasurable symptoms, like headaches and nausea. See supra Part II. 156 Chamallas, supra note 7, at 512. 157 Id. at 515. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 837 infected with gender and race bias, we should be wary of such categorical thinking.”158 Chamallas’ critiques must be located within a general framework of anti-formalism and critical legal studies.159 Indeed, Nancy Levit also argues that the law relies too much on “rules as artifacts” in distinguishing physical from ethereal injuries,160 denying science and depending on the “comfortable certainty of legal rules and forms.”161 According to Levit, “significant among the reasons why form emerges so persistently to trump substance is a continuing reluctance to accept emotional and expectancy interests.”162 This argument is somewhat circular, however, because a reluctance to accept emotional injuries is an excellent reason to create a category separating physical from emotional injuries, so long as there are reasons for this reluctance. Levit persuasively shows that this reluctance is not entirely based on problems of proof, because “[e]ven where the evidence of the ethereal injury is as certain or more certain than evidence admitted in other cases involving more traditional forms of injuries, the ethereal tort is treated as unreal, foundationless, and underserving.”163 Thus, the problem is not with these ready-made legal categories. Rather, the question is whether or not they are proxies for legitimate values and goals. Maintaining the physical/emotional hierarchy against this type of critical legal critique requires a demonstration that the categories are useful rubrics for the types of harms that we want to protect. These categories may serve important social functions even if they also may owe their initial recognition to, and perhaps to some degree continue to perpetuate, gender bias. Instead of reflecting worthwhile social attitudes, Levit says, the devaluation of emotional harm is based on notions that those who suffer emotional harm are somehow weaker, and therefore at fault for their injuries.164 She argues that this conception of emotional injury is too individualistic, and “permits little recognition of the ways in which people are socially constructed and encourages less in the way of communal 158 Id. at 530. Anti-formalists and proponents of critical legal studies eschew rigid legal categories or pure legal logic as being determinative of legal rights and duties. See Karl E. Klare, Critical Theory and Labor Relations Law, in THE POLITICS OF LAW: A PROGRESSIVE CRITIQUE 539, 544–45 (David Kairys ed., 3d ed. 1998) (“[T]he prevailing rules are not preordained by the nature of things, nor are particular case results required by legal logic. To the contrary . . . legal rules and decisions are contingent and conventional—they are products of human choice. There is always room for discretion . . . in applying the rules . . . .”). 160 Levit, supra note 7, at 174. 161 Id. 162 Id. 163 Id. 164 Id. at 174–75. 159 838 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 165 responsibility for one another’s harms.” Decisions denying compensation for emotional injuries, according to Levit, are really just “statements regarding social conformity.”166 Levit’s argument proves too much. Most of tort law, if not all law, is premised on standards to which we must all conform generally regardless of individual capacity,167 or face either legal penalties or the denial of remedies. In torts, these standards often operate against defendants, who must act reasonably and take reasonable care to avoid injuring others regardless of their own capacities for attentiveness, intelligence, and risk aversion.168 Treating emotional injuries as less worthy of protection does not force plaintiffs to behave a certain way, or even to react in particular ways. Plaintiffs are free to experience and handle their emotions as they see fit. However, like much of tort law, the physical/emotional hierarchy carves out spaces where plaintiffs cannot collect on their injuries for a variety of instrumental and deontological reasons. Indeed, there may even be feminist reasons for maintaining the distinction. Relaxing the physical/emotional construct may undermine women’s equality and autonomy in two ways. First, an intellectual climate in which emotional harm is seen as more protectable undermines agency. Feminist narratives focusing on women’s trauma may result in paternalistic efforts to limit their choices. Second, rectifying any disparate impact caused by a prioritization of physical harm would reinforce the dominant paradigm that views women as more “emotional.”169 Expanding claims for emotional harm will, in many cases, reduce autonomy and undermine notions of consent for the population that the law is trying to protect. For example, allowing intentional infliction of emotional distress claims between divorcing spouses would “affect sexual autonomy and experimentation within marriage,”170 especially if spouses fear that they may later be sued for acts to which their spouse indicated consent. Expansive emotional duties to others’ emotional well-being would also reduce autonomy for both the putative plaintiff and the would-be defendant in all manner of consensual relationships, from employer165 Id. at 176. Id. 167 See infra note 319 and accompanying text (giving an example of a standard by which society must conform to). 168 See, e.g., R.R. Co. v. Jones, 95 U.S. 439, 441–42 (1877) (“Negligence is the failure to do what a reasonable and prudent person would ordinarily have done under the circumstances of the situation, or doing what such a person under the existing circumstances would not have done.”). 169 Chamallas links the physical/emotional categories to “their respective gender[s] . . . to expose the dominant structures of thought.” Chamallas, supra note 7, at 523. 170 See Brenda Cossman et al., Gender, Sexuality, and Power: Is Feminist Theory Enough?, 12 COLUM. J. GENDER & L. 601, 626 (2003) (discussing the dissenting opinion of a Texas Supreme Court Justice who would have refused to recognize intentional infliction of emotional distress within a marriage). 166 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 839 employee to friends. These autonomy reductions will be worse for women, who are already viewed as weaker, more emotional, and more needing of protection from emotional trauma. According to Jeannie Suk, feminism’s association of women with trauma and the effort to protect women from traumatic events have created an intellectual culture in which women are viewed as incapable of making meaningful choices in certain situations and dependent on protection from their own emotional distress.171 The emergence of “abortion trauma,”172 the idea that women will later suffer distress after terminating a pregnancy, was accepted by the Supreme Court as one justification for upholding the Partial Birth Abortion Ban Act in Gonzales v. Carhart.173 Although Justice Kennedy’s concern that women will suffer “depression and loss of esteem”174 after an abortion has been sharply criticized as sexist and paternalistic, it can be linked to a wave of feminist thought and activity that began in the 1970s. In an effort to protect women from workplace sexual harassment, abusive relationships, and rape, dominant strands of the feminist movement, starting in the 1970s, advanced theories of women harmed by these ills as suffering great emotional trauma, from which they needed to be protected.175 Battered Woman Syndrome proponents attempt to justify the violence women committ against their abusive partners instead of simply leaving their partners based on notions that their trauma impaired their perceptions of their situations.176 Rape shield laws prevent defendants from cross-examining rape victims about their past sexual history to avoid the trauma of “a second brutalization in court.”177 Litigants now often claim that sexual harassment, including rude jokes and crass remarks, causes them to experience PTSD.178 The feminist theory of trauma and its proposed legislative responses “has bred sensitivity to coercion, and skepticism of consent, in conditions of gender subordination—particularly in women’s decisions and 171 Jeannie Suk, The Trajectory of Trauma: Bodies and Minds of Abortion Discourse, 110 COLUM. L. REV. 1193, 1194–97 (2010). 172 Id. at 1200–01. 173 550 U.S. 124, 159 (2007) (upholding the Partial-Birth Abortion Ban Act of 2003, 18 U.S.C. § 1531 (2006)). 174 Suk, supra note 171, at 1194–95 (quoting Carhart, 550 U.S. at 159). 175 Id. at 1197–1201. 176 See id. at 1208–09 (discussing the research of Lenore Walker, the feminist psychologist credited with proposing the official medical recognition of the trauma known as Battered Woman Syndrome). 177 Id. at 1205 (internal quotation marks omitted). 178 See id. at 1212–13 (“Psychologists have argued that workplace harassment, including overhearing sexual jokes, or even rude comments can be a diagnosable cause of PTSD. . . . Claims of PTSD in sexual harassment lawsuits are not common.”). 840 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 179 experiences regarding their bodies.” This focus on women as needing emotional protection from trauma ultimately deprives them of meaningful choices based on the view that their ability to consent is questionable. Sexual harassment laws prohibit certain behavior regardless of consent, and “[d]omestic violence mandatory arrest and prosecution policies, which exist in a majority of jurisdictions today, reflect precisely the concern that the state must take certain actions to protect women from harm, even against their own expressed views of their desires and interests.”180 Of course, intentional or unintentional torts perpetrated against women often occur in a context without choice, or without gender subordination. But, “[c]omplex changes in beliefs can spread throughout a culture.”181 The language of trauma is now also being used to protect women from instances lacking in the usual dynamics of gender subordination, such as the abortion context. For example, the Court in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey,182 which upheld portions of a Pennsylvania law requiring that physicians inform a woman considering abortion of the fetal gestational age and the nature of the procedure, reflected on the distress that a woman might feel after learning this information after an abortion and observed that “[i]t cannot be questioned that psychological well-being is a facet of health.”183 This echoes the sentiments of those who champion increased legal protection for emotional well-being. A greater blurring of the line between physical and emotional harm, especially if adopted self-consciously in deference to the emotional harms that women experience, would contribute to the intellectual movement that has elevated emotional trauma as a grave harm against which women need to be protected. For example, Martha Chamallas’s view that women are especially harmed by limitations on recovery for emotional damages184 would encourage an even greater focus on paternalism to prevent women’s emotional suffering. This risk magnifies if, as Chamallas and Kerber propose, claims for infliction of emotional distress are to be viewed as 179 Id. at 1198. Id. 181 Suk, supra note 171, at 1252. 182 505 U.S. 833 (1992). 183 Id. at 882; see also id. at 856 (noting the impact on human thinking and emotions that overruling or upholding Roe v. Wade could have on people familiar with the decision); id. at 916–17 (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (noting that the Court has upheld state regulations in the past that “enhance[d] the deliberative quality” of the decision regarding whether or not to have an abortion and further noting that these regulations were not meant to sway a woman’s decision-making one way or another in this regard). 184 See Chamallas, supra note 7, at 499 (“My hypothesis is that legal claims for emotional distress have been devalued in part because they are associated with female plaintiffs.”). 180 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 841 “women’s rights claims, as attempts to pressure the legal system to recognize and value the interests of women.”185 If the dominant view, as Chamallas believes, is that women are more emotional,186 a re-structuring of the physical/emotional hierarchy based on the idea that the current structure is unfair to women would solidify this interpretation, and bring society further down the path of believing that women need protection from emotional distress caused not only by others, but also by their own decisions. Restricting claims for emotional distress would “recognize that women are both victims and victimizers, that mutual emotional vulnerability might be a positive as well as a negative aspect of intimate relationships . . . and that seeing the emotional distress as a ‘women’s remedy’ is demeaning to women.”187 The law should respect the capacity of women and men alike to reasonably handle emotional strife. Women’s bodies should be protected, but they can bear some of the load of protecting their own minds, especially if it allows them more choice about their bodies. IV. RESUSCITATING THE PHYSICAL/EMOTIONAL DISTINCTION The feminist, scientific, and social science criticisms of the physical emotional distinction have their weaknesses. For example, the capacity of neuroscience to measure emotional distress objectively is still quite limited,188 and decisions involving what types of injuries to protect should rest on firmer theoretical grounding than the fortuities of which types of emotional trauma fMRI studies are capable of measuring. Social scientists have demonstrated that emotional injury can be as impactful as physical injury to a person’s happiness,189 but appreciating this fact, if it is a fact, does not necessitate that the law should treat emotional injury as equally worthy of protection. Emotional injuries may have been overlooked because of a devaluation of women’s perceived responses and experiences, but if there are legitimate reasons for currently maintaining the hierarchy, 185 Chamallas & Kerber, supra note 7, at 816. See Chamallas, supra note 7, at 522–23 (acknowledging that the “normative implications of gendering” alludes to women being more emotional and men having less concern for relationships). 187 See Brenda Crossman et al., supra note 170, at 626–27 (discussing the dissenting opinion of a Texas Supreme Court Justice who would have refused to recognize intentional infliction of emotional distress within a marriage). 188 See Joshua W. Buckholtz & David L. Faigman, Promises, Promises for Neuroscience and Law, 24 CURRENT BIOLOGY R861, R862 (2014), http://www.cell.com /current-biology/fulltext/S09609822(14)00920-8 (“[E]motional harm (i.e. mental suffering and emotional distress) is often treated as a secondary consideration [in determining compensatory damages] because of the difficulty in obtaining objective, quantitative measures of these mental states.”). 189 Emotional Problems After Traumatic Brain Injury, MODEL SYSTEMS KNOWLEDGE TRANSLATION CENTER 2 (2010), http://www.msktc.org/lib/docs/Factsheets/TBI_Emotional_Problems _and_TBI.pdf (“Feeling sad is a normal response to the losses and changes a person faces after [traumatic brain injury]. Feelings of sadness, frustration and loss are common after brain injury.”). 186 842 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 then neither the pedigree of the distinction nor possible disparate impact necessarily should override these reasons. Any theoretical justification of the physical/emotional distinction must be responsive to neuroscientists, social scientists, and feminists,190 while simultaneously offering further rationales for the distinction’s legitimacy. Before such a justification can be offered, however, new definitions of what is physical and what is emotional that can withstand changing technology must be devised. Our understanding of physiology can help us create better, more scientific definitions for the differences between emotional injury and bodily injury. These differences should inform our conception of how we protect physical versus emotional harm, but they should not dictate this hierarchy. Instead, we need to grapple with deeper reasons for this intuitive distinction. The physical/emotional distinction can no longer be based on the view that emotional harm is less physiological or less impactful.191 Instead, it can be justified by reference to a duty that we owe to take care of ourselves, which in turn limits the duties others owe to avoid distressing us. This duty can be situated within the various theories of tort law that encompass deontological and instrumental reasons for maintaining the physical/emotional distinction.192 Other areas of law also reflect the same themes regarding the physical/emotional hierarchy.193 A. Defining the Categories Courts and the Restatement have struggled to define the difference between emotional injury and bodily injury. Courts often do a poor job explicating this distinction, in part because some judges believe the distinction is both obvious and ineffable.194 Further, medical personnel have difficulty articulating the boundaries between one mental disorder and another, and between individuals with mental disorders and those who 190 Accordingly, Part III of this Article addresses these three groups on their own terms. See Buckholtz & Faigman, supra note 188, at R862 (“Emotional harm (i.e. mental suffering and emotional distress) is often treated as a secondary consideration [in determining compensatory damages].”). 192 See generally MARTHA CHAMALLAS & JENNIFER B. VRIGGINS, THE MEASURE OF INJURY: RACE, GENDER, AND TORT LAW (2010). 193 See J.M. BALKIN & SANFORD LEVINSON, LEGAL CANONS 122 (2000) (“In tort law, as in many other areas of contemporary law, the mechanisms that maintain the hierarchies of value are cognitive processes . . . . Embedded within the hierarchies are three contrasting categories: physical/emotional . . . .”). 194 See Messer v. Kemp, 760 F.2d 1080, 1093 (11th Cir. 1985) (“Clearly the term ‘bodily injury’ is not a phrase which requires an elaborate explanation in order to be understood.”); Rogers v. State, 396 N.E.2d 348, 352 (Ind. 1979) (holding that the element of bodily injury does not render a robbery statute unconstitutionally vague because the court “can think of no phenomenon of more common experience and understanding than the concepts of ‘bodily injury’ and ‘physical pain’”). 191 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 843 195 are not mentally ill. The Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, which lists categories of mental disorders and their manifestations, admits that “no definition adequately specifies precise boundaries for the concept of ‘mental disorder.’”196 The Restatement (Third) of Torts: Liability for Physical and Emotional Harm defines emotional harm as harm to “emotional tranquility.”197 This harm “encompasses a variety of mental states, including fright, fear, sadness, sorrow, despondency, anxiety, humiliation, depression (and other mental illnesses), and a host of other detrimental—from mildly unpleasant to disabling—mental conditions.”198 Emotional injuries manifest in the “nerve centers.”199 The Restatement stresses that an essential distinction between physical and emotional harm is whether an injury can be objectively measured200: This distinction is not precise and may be difficult to make in certain cases, but the more restrictive rules for recovery for emotional harm require that such determinations be made. The essential difference is that bodily harm usually provides objective evidence of its existence and extent while the existence and severity of emotional harm is usually dependent upon the report of the person suffering it or symptoms that are capable of manipulation or multiple explanations. Whether a specific injury constitutes bodily harm and therefore supports a claim for liability of this Restatement is a question of law for the court to decide.201 As technology improves, this focus on whether an injury is measurable will lead to increased confusion and the blurring of the physical/emotional distinction. If the law seeks to maintain the physical/emotional distinction, it must formulate clearer, more precise definitions that recognize the physiological manifestations and increasing measurability of emotional and psychological harm. Although developments in science have led legal scholars to blur the distinction between physical and emotional harm, these same developments can also inform how we distinguish these types of injuries from each other. 195 See AM. PSYCHIATRIC ASS’N, DIAGNOSTIC AND STATISTICAL MANUAL OF MENTAL DISORDERS xxxi (4th ed. 2000) (“[T]here is no assumption that each category of mental disorder is a completely discrete entity with absolute boundaries dividing it from other mental disorders or from no mental disorder.”). 196 Id. at xxx. 197 RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 4 cmt. a (2012). 198 Id. § 45 cmt. a. 199 Id. § 4 cmt. b. 200 Id. 201 Id. (internal citations omitted). 844 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 Although the bases for the distinction between physical harm and emotional harm cannot perfectly capture our intuitions and normative inclinations about the differences between the two types of harms, there are broad-brush principles that offer guidance. First, emotional harm impacts neurotransmission, where nerve cells are connected through the release of neurotransmitters in the synapses between neurons, causing electrical signals to travel from one neuron to the next.202 Because emotional harm affects neurotransmission, exchanges of chemical neurotransmitters, and electrical excitation of neurons, it does not generally cause structural changes within the brain, but instead causes functional changes, which are currently measured by fMRI.203 Physical harm, in contrast, causes structural changes to gross anatomy, and is often caused by physical trauma.204 Even something like a brain tumor, which is not caused by physical trauma, can impact cognition, emotional processing, and behavior, as well as cause structural changes beyond neurotransmission in the brain.205 In other words, brain tumors change the structure of the brain and can be excised,206 which allows us to distinguish them from something like depression that cannot be cured through surgery. This basis for distinction is not without its complications. A disorder like epilepsy, which would intuitively (and correctly) be classified as a physical injury, manifests as changes in neurotransmission that create runaway electrical excitation within the brain, causing seizures.207 202 See Robert Stufflebeam, Neurons, Synapses, Action Potentials, and Neurotransmission, CONSORTIUM ON COGNITIVE SCI. INSTRUCTION (2008), http://www.mind.ilstu.edu/curriculum/neur ons_intro/neurons_intro.php (stating that “[n]eurotransmitters are the chemical medium through which signals flow from one neuron to the next at chemical synapses” and discussing, inter alia, the in-depth process of electrical and chemical neurotransmission). For explanations on how neurotransmitters impact mood, see CARROL E. IZARD, THE PSYCHOLOGY OF EMOTIONS 51 (1991) (discussing the neural substrates of emotion, the scientific background of expressing emotion, the biological causes of emotion, and the biological functions of emotion). 203 See Thomas Novack & Tamara Bushnik, Understanding TBI: Part 2—Brain Injury Impact on Individuals Functioning, MODEL SYSTEMS KNOWLEDGE TRANSLATION CENTER (2010), http://www.msktc.org/tbi/factsheets/Understanding-TBI/Brain-Injury-Impact-On-IndividualsFunctioning (explaining the functional changes that can be caused by moderate-to-severe brain injury, such as trouble paying attention, thinking slowly, and becoming confused easily); U.C. San Diego Sch. of Med., What Is fMRI?, CENTER FOR FUNCTIONAL MRI, http://fmri.ucsd.edu/Research /whatisfmri.html (last visited Oct. 9, 2014) (describing how the data from a fMRI experiment is analyzed to identify patterns of change). 204 See Novack & Bushnik, supra note 203, at 3 (discussing the physical problems that can result from brain trauma, including coordination problems and difficulty maintaining daily structure or continued participation in an activity). 205 See id. (“There are three general types of problems that can happen after [traumatic brain injury]: physical, cognitive and emotional/behavioral problems.”). 206 See id. (discussing the severe problems that a person may face after suffering a traumatic brain injury). 207 See CTRS. FOR DISEASE CONTROL & PREVENTION, U.S. DEP’T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., CURRENT TRENDS PREVALENCE OF SELF-REPORTED EPILEPSY – UNITED STATES, 1986–1990, 43 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 845 However, these seizures are usually directly caused by physical impact or trauma, such as brain cancer, head trauma, stroke, or drug abuse,208 and thus can be considered part of physical harm. Another broad basis for the distinction between physical and emotional harm is that emotions, controlled by neural circuitry, can often be altered or alleviated without physical, pharmacological, or surgical intervention, and can sometimes be altered by decisions within the individual’s control.209 Bodily injury, even injury to the head or brain, has this feature, albeit to a much lesser extent.210 Thus, a positive thought can change one’s mood from bleak to optimistic. Seeking out social interactions can immediately make someone who has spent the day alone happier. This holds true even with more serious emotional distress.211 Psychotherapy, which normally involves no physical contact, can be as effective a cure for certain forms of depression as medications.212 In contrast, psychotherapy will certainly not be as effective as chemotherapy for a brain tumor. Physical injury often requires physical interventions and medications to avoid further deterioration, or it involves cellular changes that the body performs on its own, and the healing process is more attenuated from choices an individual makes. This basis for distinction is also imperfect, due to the interconnectivity between the mind and the body. Depression, like high blood pressure or muscular injuries, can be alleviated by physical interventions such as exercise.213 Conversely, positive thinking may MORBIDITY & MORTALITY WKLY. REP. 810, 810 (1994), available at http://www.cdc.gov/ mmwr/preview/mmwrhtml/00033483.htm (“Epilepsy is a chronic neurologic condition characterized by abnormal electrical discharges in the brain manifested as two or more unprovoked seizures.”). 208 See Seizures, MEDLINEPLUS (Feb. 10, 2014) http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/ency/article /003200.htm (providing a non-exclusive list of causes of seizures). 209 See, e.g., Elizabeth Fernandez, Emotional Benefits of Meditation Revealed in Study of Teachers, UCSF MEDICAL CENTER (Mar. 28, 2012), http://www.ucsfhealth.org/news/2012/03/ emotional_benefits_of_meditation_revealed_in_study_of_teache.html (noting that by meditating, subjects “learned to better understand the relationship between emotion and cognition”). 210 For example, an individual can choose whether or not to undergo physical therapy, and this will have some impact on the physical prognosis, but it is more attenuated. 211 There are strong links between depression and social isolation, and between companionship and the easing of depression, see V. Osteberg & C. Lennartsson, Getting By With A Little Help: The Importance of Various Types of Social Support for Health Problems, 35 SCAND J. PUB. HEALTH 197 (2007), available at http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/17454924. 212 See Graeme Whitfield & Chris Williams, The Evidence Base for Cognitive–Behavioural Therapy in Depression: Delivery in Busy Clinical Settings, 9 ADVANCES IN PSYCHIATRIC TREATMENT 21, 23–24 (2003) (compiling studies on the effectiveness of cognitive-behavioral therapy in comparison with other treatment methods). 213 See, e.g., GARY M. COONEY ET AL., EXERCISE FOR DEPRESSION (REVIEW), COCHRANE COLLABORATION 2 (2013) (noting that in thirty-five clinical trials, exercise indicated a moderate clinical effect on depression); Gretchen Reynolds, Prescribing Exercise to Treat Depression, N.Y. TIMES BLOGS (Aug. 31, 2011, 12:01 AM), http://well.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/08/31/prescribingexercise-to-treat-depression/ (reporting that 29.5% of depressed study participants who took SSRI drugs and who exercised daily for four months achieved remission of their depression). 846 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 214 improve physical symptoms and reduce mortality. The placebo effect attests to the ability of the mind’s sense of hope to improve physical symptoms to varying degrees.215 As a general rule, however, physical harm requires a physical or chemical solution that directly impacts the body to avoid further deterioration whereas emotional harm, often, does not.216 Emotional expression and perceived emotional support has been linked to increased survival in cancer patients,217 but practicing psychological coping strategies will not cure cancer by itself. These broad generalizations distinguishing physical from emotional harm can be used to form more precise definitions. As a start, physical harm, or bodily injury, could be defined as injury to any part of the body that is not the brain, plus injury to the structures of the brain through trauma or tumor, independent of changes in neural circuitry. Purely emotional harm could be defined as changes to one’s neural pathways or balance of neurotransmitters that impact one’s moods, thoughts, feelings, and cognition, and are not the immediate, direct result of physical trauma or structural changes within the body. At the margins, there may be difficulties classifying a particular injury as physical or emotional. However, this definition captures what the Restatement terms as “the ordinary distinction between bodily harm and emotional harm.”218 Fright, shame, anger, and schizophrenia are all considered emotional and psychological concerns, while brain tumors, broken bones, and inflammation of the brain are all physical injuries. A person’s being bothered by excessive noise or unpleasant odors—although neither can be easily measured—would, under these new classifications, be 214 See, e.g., Toshihiko Maruta et al., Optimists vs Pessimists: Survival Rate Among Medical Patients Over a 30-Year Period, 75 MAYO CLINICAL PROCEEDINGS 140, 142 (2000) (“The current study . . . shows that explanatory style [(how people explain life events)] . . . is significantly associated with . . . mortality beyond that due to age and sex.”). 215 One double-blind study showed that while the placebo effect does not actually decrease tumor size, it can improve pain and appetite in subjects with cancer. Gisèle Chvetzoff & Ian F. Tannock, Placebo Effects in Oncology (Review), 95 J. NAT’L. CANCER INST. 1, 19 (2003). 216 A mental condition such as schizophrenia generally requires pharmacological intervention. See Schizophrenia: Treatments and Drugs, MAYO CLINIC (Jan. 24, 2014), http://www.mayoclinic.org/ diseases-conditions/schizophrenia/basics/treatment/con-20021077 (“Medications are the cornerstone of schizophrenia treatment.”). This type of condition compromises what I will describe in the following section as “voluntariness,” so although schizophrenia would be a psychological, not a physical, disorder, if schizophrenia were proximately caused by another’s negligence (which it generally cannot be), this mental condition would be treated as on par with physical conditions in the physical/emotional hierarchy. See infra Part IV.2.b. (discussing, inter alia, how voluntariness factors in to corrective justice theory in the context of tort law). 217 See Peggy Reynolds et al., Use of Coping Strategies and Breast Cancer Survival: Results from the Black/White Cancer Survival Study, 152 AM. J. EPIDEMIOLOGY 940, 942, 944 (2000) (noting a significant correlation between emotional support and the survival rate of a segment of breast cancer patients). 218 RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 4 cmt. b (2010). 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 847 neither physical nor emotional harm because these harms directly impact the ears and nose, respectively, but likely do not cause structural or cellular change. Of course, physical injuries can cause emotional injuries and vice versa, and this Article will later address how the law should analyze cases where both types of injury occur.219 It is not necessary to accept these definitions to conclude that the law should maintain a distinction between types of harm. However, any contention that courts should maintain the categories of physical and emotional injury necessitates some basis for distinguishing between them that technology will not render obsolete. In addition, a hierarchy of the protection of physical versus emotional harm needs enduring animating rationales. The next Section argues in favor of a duty to control and regulate our own emotional health. B. The Duty to Maintain One’s Emotional Health Now that emotionally based claims are becoming more common,220 “the more important legal and policy questions of the permissible scope of liability”221 must come to the fore. However, the other arguments usually articulated for courts’ reluctance to create emotional duties, such as the fear of crushing liability and the desire to maintain a pool of funds for certain victims, cannot do all the work. Those two concerns, while valid, are question-begging because, if emotional harm is as significant as physical harm, then there should be no reason to “reserve funds for victims of other harms”222 over those who suffer from emotional distress. Although we should not create categories of liability “based on an unexamined mental-physical boundary,”223 the reasons to maintain this boundary are not merely pragmatic or relevant to the extent to which liability would increase. Rather, such reasons touch upon theoretical concerns about the types of liability that would increase and the effect on both would-be plaintiffs and would-be defendants of creating expansive emotional duties. Courts and legislatures need to decide what types of injuries they wish to protect, and if some types of injuries should be considered more protectable than others. As scientific advancements illuminate the extent to which mental distress is both physiological and significant, one would hope that mental illness would be demystified and destigmatized. However, there are still 219 See generally infra Part V (discussing the interplay between physical and emotional injuries and how the law should account for such interplay). 220 See Kontorovich, supra note 9, at 495 (“The [negligent infliction of emotional distress] tort represents the current wave of expansion and uncertainty in emotional distress liability.”). 221 Grey, Neuroscience and Emotional Harm in Tort Law, supra note 7, at 229. 222 Id. 223 Id. 848 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 compelling reasons to distinguish between physical and emotional harm. Legal obligations to protect others from emotional harm should be limited because each of us should be under a legal duty to reasonably regulate our own emotional states. This Section explores the contours of such a duty, and how it would comport with tort law theory and doctrine from other legal disciplines. 1. Preliminary Contours of the Duty This type of emotional duty would not require individuals to refrain from having or even expressing certain emotions. Instead, individuals would simply be responsible for coping with some of the emotional distress they experience, however they wish, but could not put an unreasonable burden on others. This duty operates only as a condition of seeking legal redress from those who have injured others, but the discharge of the duty may involve taking affirmative steps both before and after a tort suit. In this way, the duty serves to undermine the view that we have broad duties to protect others’ emotional well-being. Socially, individuals could be considered to owe this duty to themselves; we have an obligation to ourselves to maintain reasonable emotional control. Legally, however, the duty to reasonably regulate our own minds is one we owe each other. A duty of precisely this nature does not currently exist in tort law. The closest analogue may be the duty to mitigate damages in contract or tort law.224 This is because the failure to discharge this duty properly cannot form the basis of an independent action by others; a plaintiff who is unreasonably emotional cannot recover simply for experiencing greater emotional harm than others. Individuals must exercise mental fortitude only to the extent they wish to sue others. As will be explained below, an actual duty to mitigate, however, would be unwieldy and require proof of steps taken to mitigate emotional damages that could compromise plaintiffs’ autonomy and privacy interests in their medical and mental health decisions.225 Additionally, “[m]itigation deals only with the plaintiff’s conduct after his cause of action accrues and the defendant pleads it as an affirmative defense for which he carries the burden of proof.”226 An emotional duty is not about a plaintiff’s actions in mitigation but concerns the defendant’s responsibilities; defendants would not be 224 In tort or contract law, the duty to mitigate reduces a plaintiff’s damages if she fails to take reasonable steps to limit the extent of her injuries and therefore limit the amount of defendant’s liability. See, e.g., Kuruwa v. Meyers, 512 F. App’x 45, 47 (2d Cir. 2013) (“[A] party who claims to have suffered damage by the tort of another is bound to use reasonable and proper efforts to make the damage as small as practicable.” (internal quotation marks and citation omitted)); Steger v. Orth, 258 F. 619, 624 (2d Cir. 1919) (“The duty of a plaintiff who has been injured by a defendant, whether through tort or violation of contract, to mitigate or minimize damges, is not doubted. But what are reasonable and proper efforts . . . present . . . a question of fact.”). 225 See Kontorovich, supra note 9, at 508 (identifying problems raised by psychiatric mitigation). 226 Id. at 497. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 849 responsible for unreasonable emotional responses, no matter how much the plaintiff spent on therapy prior to or after the commission of the tort. The inquiry into this emotional duty would examine whether the severity of the plaintiff’s emotional response is reasonable, and the plaintiff could choose to establish this without cataloguing the steps he took to ensure reasonable emotional stability, although conduct both before and after the tort could be considered. Proving discharge of this duty would be the plaintiff’s burden of proof, although this question could likely be decided as a matter of law. Further, emotional duties to others may often serve as a complete bar to recovery for emotional harm, and thus can also be analogized to contributory negligence, or, in cases where a reasonable person would still suffer serious emotional harm, comparative negligence.227 Although we owe no general duty of care with respect to our own emotional responses, emotional instability that goes beyond a reasonable level does have the potential to pose a risk of unreasonable harm to others. Imposition of this type of emotional duty to reasonably regulate our own minds, even narrowly triggered only by a plaintiff’s lawsuit, thus echoes some aspects of the general duty of care we all owe to avoid causing physical harm. Questions will arise as to whether the duty is descriptive, in the sense that it reflects an average person’s emotional capacity, or normative, in the sense that it embodies moral judgments about how people ought to act. Some scholars believe that the general duty of reasonable care has a normative, almost aspirational, dimension.228 To counteract the impulse to impose a general duty of reasonable care to avoid causing emotional harm, the duty to reasonably regulate one’s emotional well-being should probably correspond to a normative, aspirational approach. Recognition of a duty to reasonably regulate one’s own emotional well-being is consistent with, and indeed responsive to, the teachings of neuroscientists, social scientists, and feminists mentioned above.229 It both recognizes the importance of emotional harm and empowers those who have suffered such harm to take ownership over their emotional states.230 A duty to tend to our own emotional health in no way negates or devalues the experience of mental distress; instead, it is a ground for concluding that tort law should not protect us from emotional harm caused by others in situations in which we should reasonably protect ourselves or mitigate our 227 See infra Part V for suggestions on doctrinal modifications. See, e.g., Alan D. Miller & Ronen Perry, The Reasonable Person, 87 N.Y.U. L. REV. 323, 326 (2012) (“We put forward and defend the argument that normative definitions are categorically preferable to positive definitions . . . .”). 229 See supra Part III (discussing, inter alia, the theories and scholarship of those who have analyzed the physical/emotional distinction). 230 See supra Part III (discussing, inter alia, how traditional tort law theories do not take emotional injuries into account). 228 850 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 own harm. These features of the duty to regulate our own mental wellbeing support a modern conception of the physical/emotional distinction that comports with various tort theories, with instrumental and deontological values embedded within these theories, and with other legal doctrines. 2. Instrumental and Deontological Justifications from Tort Theory The legal doctrines within tort law form a coherent system of values and can be understood internally, using the logic of the normative concepts and principles of tort law.231 Various tort law theories, such as efficient deterrence, corrective justice, and civil recourse theory, explain these doctrines or contribute to a deeper, more cogent understanding of what the role and function of the tort system should be. A duty to take care with respect to one’s own emotional state fits nicely into both normative and interpretive accounts of tort law and their embedded instrumental and deontological values. a. Law and Economics: Maximizing Social Welfare and Avoiding Moral Hazard The law and economics movement broadly maintains that tort law either is, or should be, a scheme that uses the threat of liability to induce actors to take cost-efficient precautions against harming others.232 Law and economics harnesses the deterrence component of tort law to maximize social welfare.233 Famously, Richard Posner has pointed to the Hand Formula as evidence that tort law aims to achieve efficient deterrence.234 According to Posner’s interpretation, negligence law, via the Hand Formula, holds an actor liable if the cost to an actor of taking a precaution against causing harm to others is less than the magnitude of the harm 231 See Zipursky, supra note 120, at 1937 (“[T]here is value to exploring the connections among the normative concepts and principles of tort law and ascertaining how they fit together within the law. First, it is likely to enhance our ability to render the law more coherent and predictable . . . . Second, it is likely to reveal . . . what the animating principles of the law are. Third, it is likely to reveal the normative questions about the validity of the law that we ought to be asking ourselves. And finally, it is likely to clarify a number of epistemic questions about the law.”). 232 See, e.g., RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW § 6.14 (6th ed. 2003) (“If compensation is the only purpose of the negligence system, it is indeed a poor system, being both costly and incomplete. Its economic function, however, is not compensation but the deterrence of inefficient accidents.”). 233 See Michael L. Rustad, Torts as Public Wrongs, 38 PEPP. L. REV. 433, 456 (2011) (“[T]he study of law and economics is interested in macrotort concerns such as reducing the cost of accidents, reallocating loss to wrongdoers, general deterrence, and rules that reflect efficiency.”). 234 See, e.g., Mesman v. Crane Pro Servs., 512 F.3d 352, 354 (7th Cir. 2008) (applying the Hand formula in the product liability context). Judge Learned Hand explained the formula in United States v. Carroll Towing Company, 159 F.2d 169, 173 (2d Cir. 1947). “[I]n algebraic terms: if the probability be called P; the injury, L; and the burden, B; liability depends upon whether B is less than L multiplied by P: i.e., whether B [is less than] PL.” Id. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 851 expected to result from the actor’s failure to take the precaution, multiplied by the risk of that harm occurring.235 For example, if it costs a store owner nine dollars each day to salt his sidewalk during winter months, and there is a one-in-ten chance each day that, without the salt, someone will slip on the store owner’s walk and incur one hundred dollars worth of injuries, the storeowner should be held liable if she does not salt her sidewalk and injury results.236 In contrast to Posner’s version of law and economics, Guido Calabresi’s brand of law and economics seeks to place the burden of liability for harm on the entity that is the “cheapest cost avoider,”237 usually a market actor who can better evaluate and internalize risks.238 Judge Calabresi is less interested than Judge Posner in making the claim that tort law, as it now stands, is well designed to identify least cost avoiders. Instead, he acknowledges that it sometimes achieves that goal, but should in any event be reformed to achieve it.239 Although it is simplistic to place these two intellectual rivals as “speaking for” the law and economics movement as it applies to tort law,240 their contributions explain and justify the deep divisions between physical and emotional injuries. If the physical/emotional distinction is abolished, a general duty to avoid causing emotional harm would exist that is identical to the one that protects against physical harm. Yet, internalization of others’ emotional costs would diminish social welfare because physical injury and emotional injury are not similarly situated. Forcing defendants to internalize the costs of causing emotional trauma is not only untenable because of the pragmatic concern that emotional liability is potentially limitless, given the number of people who could be distressed by a given action, but beyond that, it is difficult for defendants to account for the emotional benefits of their actions. There is no 235 See Mesman, 512 F.3d at 354 (discussing the Hand Formula and the necessity of weighing a risk of injury against the cost of averting it); see also Russell B. Korobkin & Thomas S. Ulen, Law and Behavioral Science: Removing the Rationality Assumption from Law and Economics, 88 CALIF. L. REV. 1051, 1096 (2000) (“Traditional law and economics suggests that precaution is efficient when its benefits outweigh its costs and that tort law should impose liability for negligence when an actor fails to take efficient precaution but not when he fails to take inefficient precaution.”). 236 Note that the $9 cost of salting is less than the $10 expected value of the harm. 237 GUIDO CALABRESI, THE COSTS OF ACCIDENTS: A LEGAL AND ECONOMIC ANALYSIS 138, 262–63 (1970). 238 See id. at 163–64 (“[O]ne of the two parties may, in practice, be far more able than the other to evaluate the accident risk . . . . And if this is the case, his activity is better suited . . . to bear the initial loss. . . . [T]he choice of loss bearers depends on which of the two parties to the bargain can inject the cost into the price of the goods or service most cheaply.”). 239 See id. at 312 (“[A] mixed system [between fault and other liability systems] can be developed which does all the things we want in the way of accident cost reduction better than the fault system and does them consistently with our sense of justice.”). 240 See, e.g., id. at 1 (describing Posner’s brand of law and economics to contrast it with Guido Calabresi’s and Richard Epstein’s). 852 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 accompanying dollar value of these benefits in the same way that there are economic gains that can be accounted for when a store owner decides whether it is worth his time to salt his walkway. There are emotional benefits to third parties that cannot be accounted for or internalized by putative defendants whenever an emotional loss is suffered, which occurs far more often than physical benefits to others when an individual suffers physical harm. Further, because many otherwise justifiable actions cause a wide variety of negative emotional responses, deterring others from causing emotional harm will cause losses in social utility in a way that does not arise with respect to the general duty of care to prevent physical harm. Consider the decision to fire an employee. Even if this decision does not violate any employment laws, is the best decision for the company’s financial growth, will ultimately benefit the person hired in the employee’s place more than it will harm the employee, and the fired employee will actually be happier or better off in the long run, the termination of employment might well cause a strong negative emotional reaction, sometimes even resulting in short- or long-term depression.241 Allowing this emotional distress to be generally actionable would place a thumb on the scale against firing the employee, a socially inefficient decision in the long run absent consideration of emotional consequences (and perhaps even when considering emotional consequences). The fear of an unmeritorious lawsuit alone might render an employer less likely to fire an employee, even in the absence of negligence. Given that the negligence standard will likely be ill-defined in cases implicating a general duty to avoid causing emotional harm,242 there would be a justifiable concern that a firing decision, or implementation of that decision, was made without due care for a plaintiff’s emotional health. Firing decisions should be based on the suitability of an employee to her position, not on the concern that the decision will cause emotional distress to the plaintiff greater than the gains in productivity to the company.243 Employers should not be forced to subsidize the emotional stability—generically—of their employees. Regrettable disincentives based on fear of lawsuits also exist in other 241 See Nunes–Baptista v. WFM Haw., LLC, Civil No. 11–00104 LEK–BMK, 2012 WL 1536075, at *9 (D. Haw. Apr. 30, 2012) (granting summary judgment on an intentional infliction of emotional distress claim where the plaintiff alleged that “[h]er termination caused depression, as she was extremely emotionally upset that she was terminated for an unjust reason”). 242 The duty owed to others to avoid causing emotional harm would have to be borrowed from cultural norms. One way to clarify this duty would be to tie it to violations of other, independent interests, such as the duty to take reasonable care to avoid causing physical injury. See infra Part V (proposing this solution). 243 Great social peril may accompany this over-consideration of others’ emotional well-being. Consider a jilted lover who believes that if his beloved would just rekindle their romance, he would feel so much happier. Individuals should not be held responsible in this way for others’ emotional welfare. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 853 areas of negligence, and in employment law generally, but this concern is compounded in the emotional distress arena as the emotional distress to a plaintiff is often offset by emotional gains to another party. Prevention and harm are not the only variables when dealing with emotional harm; there is the emotional gain, difficult to predict and measure, to third parties who benefitted from whatever decision caused the emotional distress. The Hand Formula breaks down because, while economic benefits to the company can be accounted for,244 and while physical gains can offset physical losses,245 emotional benefits that would offset predicted emotional damages calculations would be nearly impossible to measure and incorporate. If opening the door to emotional losses on one side of the Hand Formula necessarily opened the door to emotional gains on the other side, then courts would have to contend with negligent behavior that causes physical harm where the defendant wants to include foregone emotional benefits in the burden of avoiding the harm. Accounting for the emotional highs and lows to every party involved in every decision would greatly skew society’s vision of which actions are appropriate. This is because almost every decision that increases overall social welfare is accompanied by emotional distress for some party, and yet in many cases such a decision also improves the emotional situations of other parties. From giving a student frank but critical feedback on a paper, to failing the student, to giving a romantic partner frank but critical appraisal of his appearance, to terminating the relationship, the emotional gains and losses are myriad. An event that causes a person emotional injury in the short-term may actually make the person better off, even looking only at the emotional axis, in the long run. Benefits to an injured party and third parties that exceed losses are less likely to occur when someone inflicts physical injury upon an individual. With intentional physical injury, usually the only people who benefit, and likely not in the long run, are the perpetrators or sadistic bystanders. In the case of a negligently inflicted physical injury, there will be some gain to the perpetrator from the benefits of the negligent action, like the ability to drive faster or avoid cleaning ice in front of one’s store. These benefits can be accounted for using the Hand Formula as part of the cost of preventing the injury. Plus, when negligent action results in physical injury, the defendant likely could have performed the action she wanted, and received many of the benefits of performing that action, so long as she took reasonable precautions to reduce the chances of physical injury. In many of those cases, the defendant’s autonomy would be preserved and the injury 244 A company will stay in business if, after applying the Hand Formula and determining it must prevent certain types of harm, its profits exceed those prevention costs. 245 A company can account for wear and tear on its employees when calculating the costs of preventing particular accidents. 854 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 would not have occurred. But no matter how gently an employer fires an employee—and query whether society should incentivize treating people as gently as possible—a great deal of emotional distress will arise from a termination decision. Thus, when an action causes physical injury, there are reasons to think that it is more likely to be socially inappropriate or harmful than an action that causes emotional harm. An action that causes physical injury is less likely to have positive consequences, and it is more likely that the perpetrator could have reaped many of the action’s benefits without causing harm by taking more precautionary measures.246 It is also more likely that the defendant can properly account for all the harms and benefits that result from her behavior when making rational calculations about whether to engage in the behavior. Of course, emotional harm is still a true harm, and thus should be reflected in the Hand Formula if courts wish to maximize social welfare. But, to the extent that individuals wish to avoid emotional harm,247 the law should create incentives for plaintiffs to minimize their own emotional distress. Learning to cope emotionally is an important skill for all individuals, and is linked to improved physical health as well as emotional well-being.248 Creating a society where individuals believe that they have control over their emotional destinies will inspire and encourage others to face emotional adversity and take responsibility for overcoming it. Individuals should not repress their emotions. However, focusing on the indignation of an emotional upset tends to amplify the sense of distress.249 Knowing that someone has legally wronged you by breaching a legal obligation to your emotional state would increase that sense of indignation. If this harm is minimized, defendants can engage in more socially desirable behaviors, and such autonomy promotes instrumental goals and has inherent value. 246 Sporting events or dangerous tasks that often result in physical injury but are socially desirable are not analogous to employment terminations, relationship strife, or offensive speech because often in the latter-type cases, the emotionally distressed party did not wish for the precipitating event to occur. 247 If individuals do not seek to minimize emotional harms, choose to neglect their emotional health in favor of other goals, or prefer to experience extreme emotional highs and lows, the law does not, as Levit argues, mandate conformity. These individuals cannot, then, seek compensation from others. See supra Part II.B. (discussing courts’ typical treatment of purely emotional injuries in the eggshell psyche and parasitic damages contexts and how they do not award compensation for emotional injuries unless such injuries manifest themselves in connection with some other independent harm). 248 See supra Part III.A (discussing the ability of medical technology and neuroscience to improve our understanding of emotional harms and how they interact with physical harms). 249 For an interesting account of the challenges of viewing individuals as victims, see Martha Minow, Surviving Victim Talk, 40 UCLA L. REV. 1411, 1431 (1993) (“Describing yourself as a victim has a self-fulfilling and self-perpetuating feature; and yet, failing to acknowledge or assert one’s victimization leaves the harm unaddressed and the perpetrators unchallenged.”). 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 855 Treating the defendant as insurer of the plaintiff’s emotional wellbeing also poses difficulties that do not exist in the realm of physical injuries. Allowing broad compensation for emotional injuries creates “moral hazard”250 problems. Knowing that a defendant must basically insure the full extent of a plaintiff’s injuries “result[s] in inefficiently low levels of post-injury care by plaintiffs and systematic overcompensation.”251 Creating a duty to mitigate emotional harm, similar to the duty to mitigate physical injury, could alleviate this moral hazard problem, but any possible standards for mitigation of emotional distress would be nearly impossible to administer.252 Forcing injured plaintiffs to seek psychiatric care or pharmacological intervention prior to suing, and then making these treatments part of a court record, compromises plaintiffs’ autonomy and privacy.253 This type of duty to mitigate others’ emotional distress also creates second-order moral hazard issues that do not arise in cases of physical injury. A plaintiff not needing treatments for emotional distress caused by a defendant’s conduct may undertake them anyway, knowing that the defendant must pay plaintiff’s mitigation costs.254 Psychotherapy and unnecessary pharmacological solutions are much more appealing than treatments for nonexistent physical injuries, and with the defendant as the insurer, there is little reason for the plaintiff to consider these costs efficiently. We may all benefit from extensive mental health treatment, whether or not it is related to a particular emotional injury. However, the vast array of mental health problems in the United States should not be addressed haphazardly through the tort system255 by holding individual defendants accountable for the emotional health of others. Unlike physical maladies, mental distress is often difficult to trace to a root cause. Any particular defendant should not bear the entire extent of someone’s emotional experience, which may be informed by other past events and traumas. The care of our nation’s mental health generally should be dealt with systematically through public health insurance, other public health initiatives, or using market-based solutions like private health insurance systems through employers. Allowing widespread compensation 250 Moral hazard is a phenomenon where those with insurance tend to incur greater losses than the uninsured. Tom Baker, On the Genealogy of Moral Hazard, 75 TEX. L. REV. 237, 238–39 (1996). 251 Kontorovich, supra note 9, at 491. 252 Id. at 507–08. 253 See id. at 507–12 (discussing the ways that a duty to mitigate psychiatric damages would uniquely cause problems regarding the autonomy and the privacy of the individual upon whom the duty is imposed). 254 See id. at 510–11 (discussing the problem of the “merry mitigator” in this context). 255 Fifty percent of Americans will experience mental illness at some point during their lifetime, and fewer than half of those people will ever get treatment. Rebecca Spain Broches, Creating Continuity: Improving the Quality of Mental Health Care Provided to Justice-Involved New Yorkers, 21 GEO. J. ON POVERTY L. & POL’Y 91, 91 (2013) (citations omitted). 856 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 for emotional injuries, even with a duty to mitigate, would incentivize plaintiffs to seek more mental health care than the defendant’s conduct made necessary. Because of the difficulties inherent in creating a duty to mitigate emotional harm, Eugene Kontorovich has concluded that “courts must limit moral hazard in emotional distress cases by limiting the scope of liability or recovery.”256 Of course, there are many instances where a defendant’s intentional or negligent conduct causes psychological issues that require a great deal of time, attention, money, and often pharmacological intervention to remedy. There will be instances where plaintiffs cannot be held responsible for their emotional distress and should be compensated for these costs.257 However, to the extent individuals have mental infirmities that render them more susceptible to emotional upset, the law should encourage these individuals to seek help ahead of time by making it clear that they ordinarily cannot be compensated later. Overall, the law does not serve social welfare by holding defendants responsible for behavior that might cause generally unpleasant but tolerable levels of emotional distress, or serious yet extraordinary emotional responses.258 Preventing and treating emotional upheavals, if individuals wish to avoid them, is a burden usually best placed on the person experiencing the emotion. Within reason, we want people to learn to take control of their emotional lives and to take emotional issues seriously, both before an emotionally disturbing incident and afterwards. Because we have more control over our emotional responses than our physical responses,259 a refusal to create a general duty to take reasonable care to avoid causing emotional harm to others would place the burden on the least cost avoider, the individual, to both seek therapy or medical assistance for pre-existing mental health conditions and get help, or learn coping strategies, for emotional injuries after the fact. An individual may not have the ability to control his immediate emotional response to an event, but society expects him to control his behavior,260 and he can control his long-term processing of the emotion. To the extent that an emotional injury is so serious that it overtakes or incapacitates a plaintiff who is not suffering from prior mental 256 Kontorovich, supra note 9, at 491–92. See infra Part V (noting that in the context of criminal law, plaintiffs sometimes should be compensated for emotional harm because the duty to maintain one’s emotional health is exercised properly). 258 If an event or action is so distressing that it would cause serious mental anguish to a reasonable person, then perhaps the balance of instrumental values should shift to allowing compensation for that individual’s emotional injuries. Limitations on the duty to control one’s own mind will be discussed infra in Part V. 259 This argument is fleshed out supra in Part IV.B. 260 Although suffering from extreme emotional outrage when committing crimes may receive lesser penalties for those crimes, this type of emotional outrage does not completely excuse the crime committed. 257 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 857 261 illness, tort law may want to offer compensation, but this would not entail creating a general duty of care to avoid emotional injuries or placing no duty on plaintiffs to control their own emotional responses. b. Corrective Justice: Notions of Fault Require Mental Control Corrective justice is a deontological theory of tort law that treats the tort-law duty to pay compensatory damages as a legal recognition of a moral duty to repair incurred by an injurer who wrongfully causes harm to a victim.262 The physical/emotional distinction, and a modern justification based on duties to maintain our own emotional health, should consider defendants less responsible, and therefore less at fault, for others’ emotional distress. Fault is the animating principle of corrective justice.263 Defendants must provide compensation for harm that is wrongful, thus repairing the disequilibrium created by a wrongfully caused loss. There are various forms of corrective justice theory; some focus more on repair and wrongful losses, and some focus more on causation.264 As with law and economics, many versions of corrective justice break down if emotional injury is given parity with physical injury. A duty to maintain one’s own emotional health would comport with theories based on corrective justice. Corrective justice generally relies on human agency and does not fault defendants for losses properly attributed to plaintiffs.265 According to Jules Coleman, a major proponent of corrective justice, losses can be wrongful if they invade upon a legally protected right, and “[t]o say that I have a right to something is to say that I, not you or anybody else, has control over its use.”266 Under Ernest J. Weinrib’s particular view of corrective justice, “a wrongful act is one which shows disrespect for the equal free agency of another and harms her in manifesting such disrespect or by injuring her 261 See infra Part V for proposals along these lines. See Benjamin C. Zipursky, Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice, 91 GEO. L.J. 695, 700 (2003) (“One who causes a wrongful injury to another is obligated to compensate the other for the injury caused. The existence of such an obligation, quite apart from the law, flows from the fact that the wrongful injurer is responsible for the injury wrongfully inflicted on the other.”). 263 See Jules L. Coleman, Tort Law and the Demands of Corrective Justice, 67 IND. L.J. 349, 351 (1992) (“In this essay, I want to present the beginnings of an account of tort law that takes the principle of fault liability seriously. Fault is central both to the institution of tort law and, in my view, to its ultimate moral defensibility. I want to provide here a moral foundation for the fault principle in the principle of corrective, not retributive, justice.”). 264 See id. at 699 n.18 (cataloguing the theories of various scholars of competing schools of corrective justice). 265 See G. Edward White, The Unexpected Persistence of Negligence, 1980–2000, 54 VAND. L. REV. 1337, 1356 (2001) (“Corrective justice arguments would support this trend, suggesting that a plaintiff’s recovery should be reduced to the extent, and only to the extent, that his fault contributed to his injury.”). 266 Coleman, supra note 263, at 372. 262 858 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 267 capacity to exercise free will.” These statements work well when considering physical harms caused by others. I control the use of my body, and any actions to which I did not consent and that injure my body violate that right and impose upon my ability to make decisions about my body.268 However, in the case of emotional injury, someone’s wrongful action may have caused me to suffer emotional upset, but, in most cases, my mind was not invaded by that person’s actions and my free will was not disrupted. The harms are therefore attributable to me. Under corrective justice theory, this distinction between physical invasions and mental invasions must hold. If my mind is invaded every time someone’s actions cause emotional upset in the same way that my body is invaded every time someone’s actions cause me physical injury, then everyone’s mind is invaded for good or ill each time we interact with others and experience new thoughts and emotions. The entire scheme of free will, fault, and wrongdoing that corrective justice requires, even the wrongdoing entailed in the defendant’s action that caused the emotional upset in the first place, evaporates. Corrective justice theory provides that “injurers are liable for all and only the causal results of their agency.”269 This presupposes that each individual generally exercises control over her own mind.270 You cannot have fault principles without at least a weak notion of agency or free will,271 and you cannot advance as strong a theory of free will without the notion that, at least to some extent, individuals control their own emotions and thoughts to a greater extent than they can control their bodies’ reaction to physical harm.272 267 Ken Kress, Introduction: Formalism, Corrective Justice and Tort Law, 77 IOWA L. REV. i, iv (1992). 268 This also accords with Richard Epstein’s strict liability theory of corrective justice. See Richard A. Epstein, A Theory of Strict Liability, 2 J. LEGAL STUD. 151, 152 (1973) (“The . . . theory . . . of strict liability[] holds the defendant prima facie liable for the harm caused whether or not either of the two further conditions relating to negligence and intent is satisfied.”). 269 Coleman, supra note 263, at 350. 270 However, “if the basic conditions for attributing moral agency to a defendant are lacking—as, for example, when the defendant is pushed into the plaintiff by another party—then corrective justice must excuse her.” Christopher H. Schroeder, Corrective Justice, Liability for Risks, and Tort Law, 38 UCLA L. REV. 143, 148 (1990). 271 Coleman believes that there can be fault without blame, such as in cases when a defendant acts negligently and harms someone without purpose. To hold a defendant at fault still requires the view that she is responsible for not taking precautions that could have prevented the harm. See Coleman, supra note 263, at 370 (emphasizing that the corrective justice principle is concerned with the consequences of the acts, not of the culpability of the actor, and that a person should be held negligent if he or she does not comply with the objective standard of conduct). 272 In instances where a defendant’s actions have resulted in such emotional turmoil as to diminish our understanding of voluntariness, the defendant then could be deemed at fault. See supra Part V 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 859 Common sense experience, reflected in a good deal of legal doctrine,273 informs us that emotional upset is, to a much greater extent than physical injury, within our control.274 Although choices about diet, exercise, sleep, and the amount of stress in our lives impact our susceptibility to physical disease, we cannot “will” the disease away once it manifests. Further, these lifestyle choices serve only to mitigate risk factors for illness; they are often not choices everyone can afford to make; and we often have very little ability, without great effort and expense, to overcome physical injuries once they arise. There is little that can be done, through force of will, to heal a broken bone, a gunshot wound, or even acid reflux disease. If we can more easily control our minds, we should be less inclined to think it has been invaded, even when others cause us emotional harm. The idea that we have relatively more control over our emotional state than our physical state is connected to the notion that our mind is, in fact, who we are. The functioning of our mind is inextricably connected with our identity in ways that our physical presence is not. Losing a limb or cutting one’s hair may change one’s behavior and even, to some degree, one’s personality, and it may impact one’s identity to the extent that someone’s identity is bound up in her physical capacities or physical health. However, changes in one’s physical state do not impact one’s identity in the same way as our mental, emotional, and psychological growth. Further, we can use our rational faculties to promote that growth, and to accept and surpass painful emotional responses. An analogy to the phenomenon of hedonic adaptation can shed light on this view. As noted earlier, individuals adjust to serious, disabling injuries and often report similar levels of happiness pre- and post-injury.275 Sean Hannon Williams, for example, writes that individuals who suffer extreme physical trauma adjust to their diminished capacities and maintain their levels of happiness by altering their goals, preferences, and ideals—the very essence of their identities.276 A paraplegic former athlete, for example, might develop an interest in music after suffering a disabling injury.277 To Williams, this forced self-alteration, which causes an identity (explaining the different theories and approaches that courts can take when dealing with emotional distress tort cases, both when the damage is slight and when the damage is great). 273 See supra Part IV.B. (discussing a social science experiment that concluded that the relationship between happiness and mental health is stronger than the relationship between happiness and physical health). 274 See supra Part III.A. (explaining the history of the court’s reluctance to compensate for emotional harm). 275 See Sean Hannon Williams, Self-Altering Injury: The Hidden Harms of Hedonic Adaptation, 96 CORNELL L. REV. 535, 540 (2011). 276 Id. at 566–67. 277 See id. (defining “adaptation” as when a person changes what he or she enjoys in order to accommodate the new disability). 860 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 “transformation[,] is almost certainly a harm from the perspective of the predisability self.”278 Even if we accept that premise,279 the way we adjust to emotional upset is to adjust who we are. Our emotional reactions, and the new identities we form to deal with these reactions, are part of us. People have profound abilities to find ways to mitigate their emotional and psychological despair, and, as mentioned earlier, the law should encourage this.280 Individuals should also be held responsible for doing so. The way that they approach doing so is bound up in their identities. An individual’s desire and ability to find that new approach, and the resulting approach, are a fundamental part of her character. A duty to control one’s own emotional state would acknowledge that we can control our own emotional states, and, in fact, we are our emotional states. Under this approach, the law should hold an individual responsible for attempts to cope with emotional suffering, both because he has the capacity to respond in productive ways to emotional distress and because the ways in which he responds form part of his “self.” Although it may be true that no action of the mind is truly “voluntary,” and that we have very little control over our emotional states, our conception of ourselves as our minds signifies that “we” are our emotional states and how we regulate them. We are in control of that growth, because that growth both is and becomes who we are. In even stronger terms, Martha Nussbaum contends that our emotional responses are defined by our evaluative judgments and based on our thoughts and ideas about the state of objects that we deem necessary to our flourishing.281 Nussbaum’s grief at the death of her mother, for example, is an experience of the thought that her beloved mother is lost forever.282 This grief is a reflection of the cognitive conclusion that she values the idea of mothers generally and values her mother specifically, both for Nussbaum’s own flourishing and for her mother’s sake.283 The emotions we experience are not fundamentally different from our thoughts and, in fact, have been overlooked as a source of wisdom in moral and ethical philosophy.284 Corrective justice faults defendants for wrongfully invading the rights 278 Id. at 567. Many of these disabled individuals, and many people in general, report being glad for the personal struggles in their lives, which have made them who they are. See id. (quoting a paralysis patient saying that he or she did not have to mourn his or her losses in order to maintain a positive selfimage). 280 See supra Part IV.B. (explaining the various reasons why mitigating emotional damages is a beneficial mechanism). 281 See MARTHA NUSSBAUM, UPHEAVALS OF THOUGHT: THE INTELLIGENCE OF EMOTIONS 69–70 (2001) (using examples to explain the difference between evaluative judgments and judgments that arise in the context of particular situations). 282 Id. at 39. 283 Id. at 52–53. 284 Id. at 25–31. 279 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 861 of plaintiffs, but breaks down unless we view our emotional responses as part of our personal agency. If a plaintiff was not wrongfully injured in the same way, then a defendant should not owe the same sort of duty to repair as with physical injury.285 c. Civil Recourse Theory: Elevation of Human Agency Civil recourse theory maintains that tort law empowers victims of wrongfully inflicted injuries to respond to those who have injured them.286 Plaintiffs, however, should not be entitled to seek redress for injuries if they have failed to heed their duty to exercise reasonable emotional control. The originators of civil recourse theory, John Goldberg and Benjamin Zipursky, demonstrate in Unrealized Torts how their theory can be invoked to salvage the disparate treatment of physical and emotional injury.287 Civil recourse theory gives plaintiffs remedies in certain situations, but the law “allocat[es] . . . responsibility for certain aspects of plaintiffs’ well-being to the plaintiffs themselves.”288 By treating physical and emotional harm differently, tort law sets the “normative ideal of holding plaintiffs responsible for their personal responses.”289 Just as a parent might downplay a child’s hurt feelings to minimize emotional preoccupation with an incident at school,290 courts can discourage citizens from making legal mountains out of personal molehills by refusing to allow claims for pure emotional injury.291 This “provides a legal version of norm-setting and norm-articulation, where the norm is one of fostering the thick-skinned response of getting on with life . . . .”292 This account of tort law’s treatment of emotional harm necessitates a belief in what Goldberg and Zipursky call the “agency concern,”293 the 285 If a plaintiff is able to have more control over his emotions, then a defendant should not be held accountable for the consequences. See Coleman, supra note 263, at 370 (explaining that since corrective justice relies on the theory of culpability and retribution, we should only punish those who create negative consequences). 286 See Andrew S. Gold, The Taxonomy of Civil Recourse, 39 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 65, 66–67 (2011) (“On the civil recourse view, where one individual violates the rights of another, the wronged party is entitled to seek recourse in a court of law by initiating a private right of action. In other words, private law is designed so that a wronged party may act against the wrongdoer through a state-provided venue.”). 287 See Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1679–83 (illustrating how a person should control his or her emotions, but can recover damages in certain circumstances). 288 Id. at 1683. 289 Id. at 1681. 290 Id. at 1680. 291 Id. at 1680–81. 292 Id. at 1681. 293 Id. at 1677 (internal quotation marks omitted). As Goldberg and Zipursky explain, the “‘equivalence-of-harms’ thesis” articulates the idea that, to someone who suffers harm, the type of harm is irrelevant, and only the magnitude or severity of the harm matters. Id. at 1668. Tort law’s 862 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 view that “[e]motional harm is often, though not always, in the control of, and therefore the responsibility of, the victim.”294 In a narrative that explains tort law’s reluctance to compensate plaintiffs for emotional injuries, the agency concern encompasses the idea that individuals bear responsibility for their emotional responses.295 Our legal system “refuses to deem emotional injury as a fact impervious to the plaintiff’s own will.”296 According to the agency concern, “[e]motional distress is not simply an uncontrolled or uncontrollable reflex, as is the bodily response to a blow or a toxin. It is a response mediated by the mind of the plaintiff.”297 This view echoes the instrumental and deontological reasons for treating emotional responses as belonging to the plaintiff mentioned in the previous subparts. Taking the concept of the agency concern further—and perhaps to normative territory into which Goldberg and Zipursky would not venture— I suggest that to allow plaintiffs to be compensated for their emotional responses would either signal to individuals that these responses are not within their control or would reward individuals for their lack of selfcontrol. Plaintiffs should not seek recourse from defendants, in the ordinary course of things, for their emotional injuries, but should instead look within themselves.298 The agency concern, and this Article’s more expansive articulation of the idea that individuals have a duty to regulate their own emotional distress, fits into a number of philosophical schemes regarding notions of the self, autonomy, and consent. The perception of each individual as the keeper of his own mind better enables individuals to be considered actors with agency, empowered to make decisions voluntarily. The idea that we, absent extreme circumstances, can be rattled into losing control of our emotional states, and thus our ability to make rational decisions, would nullify contracts, erode notions of fault, and allow the law an extremely paternalistic reach. 3. Echoes of the Physical/Emotional Hierarchy in Other Legal Disciplines To the extent that we value coherence in the law, maintaining the treatment of emotional harm looks quite odd under the equivalence-of-harms thesis but is resolved by presuming that courts account for the agency concern. Id. at 1668, 1677. 294 Id. at 1677. 295 Id. at 1683. 296 Id. at 1685. 297 Id. at 1681. 298 Of course, different people have different capacities for “toughing out” emotional injuries. There is a tension in the law between protecting the vulnerable and facilitating positive manifestations of strength. Resolution of this tension is not critical to this Article, which maintains that facilitating an atmosphere that encourages personal responsibility for one’s emotions ultimately benefits most people, although it may benefit some more than others. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 863 physical/emotional hierarchy based on a duty to regulate one’s own emotional health can unify many of the foundational, and often uncontroversial, insights embedded in tort law, First Amendment law, and criminal law. These legal disciplines share common intuitions, including greater solicitude towards physical harm and the view that physical harm compromises voluntariness more than emotional harm. a. The Emotional Costs of Free Speech Tort law’s reluctance to create duties to take care against distressing others is broadly consistent with America’s unique approach to free speech law.299 The First Amendment, as articulated in modern times, stands opposed to interventions by the government into the “marketplace of ideas,” which both preserves individual autonomy and benefits the collective.300 This approach, which distinguishes the United States from other Western democracies,301 has been understood by the Supreme Court to require the toleration of various forms of speech that predictably causes emotional harm.302 In the twentieth century, as tort law expanded its protection of emotional harms,303 First Amendment doctrine expanded in the opposite direction, refusing to safeguard society from offensive, uncivilized, and hateful speech.304 Courts consistently reject the calls by scholars and aggrieved plaintiffs to remove “hate speech” from the ambit of protected 299 According to Kathleen Sullivan, two competing visions of free speech exist in some tension: free speech as political equality and free speech as liberty. Kathleen M. Sullivan, Two Concepts of Freedom of Speech, 124 HARV. L. REV. 143, 144–45 (2010). Recent decisions, like Citizens United, represent a victory for the libertarian conception of free speech, which “treats with skepticism all government efforts at speech suppression that might skew the private ordering of ideas.” Id. at 145; see Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 558 U.S. 310, 365 (2010) (holding that a federal law— which prohibited unions, corporations, and non-profit organizations from broadcasting campaign commercials within a certain time period of elections—violated the First Amendment as an unconstitutional restriction on free speech). 300 See, e.g., Consol. Edison Co. of N.Y., Inc. v. Pub. Serv. Comm’n of N.Y., 447 U.S. 530, 537– 38 (1980) (“If the marketplace of ideas is to remain free and open, governments must not be allowed to choose which issues are worth discussing or debating . . . .” (internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting Police Department of Chi. v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 96 (1972))); Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. 476, 484 (1957) (“[The First Amendment] was fashioned to assure unfettered interchange of ideas for the bringing about of political and social changes desired by the people.”). 301 Arguably, America’s free speech protections are more expansive in vision than anywhere else in the world. See Robert A. Sedler, An Essay on Freedom of Speech: The United States v. The Rest of the World, 2006 MICH. ST. L. REV. 377, 379 (“[T]he constitutional protection afforded to freedom of speech in the United States is seemingly unparalleled anywhere else in the world . . . .”). 302 See, e.g., Rebecca Tushnet, More Than a Feeling: Emotion and the First Amendment, 127 HARV. L. REV. 2392, 2395 (2014) (“[T]he deliberate infliction of emotional distress on specific targets is . . . regularly protected by the First Amendment.” (emphasis omitted)). 303 See supra Part II. 304 See G. Edward White, The First Amendment Comes of Age: The Emergence of Free Speech in Twentieth-Century America, 95 MICH. L. REV. 299, 300–01 (1996) (discussing how First Amendment issues have pervaded American constitutional jurisprudence in past decades). 864 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW 305 [Vol. 47:809 306 speech, as is the norm in most other Western democracies. The claim that bigoted, vitriolic speech causes unique emotional injury and can silence members of socially vulnerable groups has had little traction in the face of modern free speech doctrine.307 The Supreme Court has explicitly stated, at least when speech involves matters of public concern, that individuals must bear the emotional costs of speech as part of living in a free society.308 Courts have often minimized or devalued these emotional costs, cautioning individuals that they need to develop a “thick skin” to allow for robust debate and free expression.309 Indeed, the fact that a behavior has emotional costs is, in large part, what renders the behavior speech under the First Amendment. Without the distinction between physical and emotional harm, our rationales for protecting speech are undermined. The somewhat blurry line between speech, which is presumptively protected, and conduct, which is generally regulable, is premised at least in part on the notion that pure speech is a communicative act that directly causes only emotional harm, whereas conduct involves direct, physical, tangible interactions and harm.310 Speech 305 For an influential, although ultimately unavailing, example of arguments in favor of restrictions on hateful speech, see generally MARI MATSUDA ET AL., WORDS THAT WOUND: CRITICAL RACE THEORY, ASSAULTIVE SPEECH, AND THE FIRST AMENDMENT (1993). 306 See Michel Rosenfeld, Hate Speech in Constitutional Jurisprudence: A Comparative Analysis, 24 CARDOZO L. REV. 1523, 1524, 1529–30, 1541 (2003) (arguing that freedom of speech in the United States is “shaped above all by individualism and libertarianism,” whereas in other Western democracies, freedom of speech is shaped by “honor and dignity”). 307 Cf. David Goldberger, Sources of Judicial Reluctance to Use Psychic Harm as a Basis for Suppressing Racist, Sexist and Ethnically Offensive Speech, 56 BROOK. L. REV. 1165, 1166 (1991) (“One of the most puzzling aspects of the judiciary’s stance protecting racially, ethnically and sexually offensive public speech is that it has rarely questioned the validity of the claims of harm. On the contrary, the judiciary has often conceded that offensive speech causes emotional harm while ruling that such speech, nonetheless, is entitled to constitutional protection.”). 308 In the Supreme Court’s eight-to-one majority opinion in Snyder v. Phelps, 131 S. Ct. 1207 (2011), which set aside a multi-million dollar jury award for intentional infliction of emotional distress, id. at 1214, 1221, Chief Justice Roberts asserted: Speech is powerful. It can stir people to action, move them to tears of both joy and sorrow, and—as it did here—inflict great pain. On the facts before us, we cannot react to that pain by punishing the speaker. As a Nation we have chosen a different course—to protect even hurtful speech on public issues to ensure that we do not stifle public debate. Id. at 1220. 309 E.g., Besler v. Bd. of Ed. of W. Windsor-Plainsboro Reg’l Sch. Dist., 993 A.2d 805, 823 (N.J. 2010) (“[F]ree speech is not for the fainthearted. [Public] officials must be thick-skinned enough to tolerate the uninhibited and robust debate on public issues that the First Amendment demands.”). 310 See Kathleen M. Sullivan, Resurrecting Free Speech, 63 FORDHAM L. REV. 971, 976 (1995) (“The distinction between mind and body—or, as it is usually called in this context, speech and conduct, or expression and action—holds that speech is privileged above conduct in the sense that government may properly regulate the clash of bodies but not the stirring of hearts and minds.”). But see John Greenman, On Communication, 106 MICH. L. REV. 1337, 1340 (2008) (“Some scholars argue that communicative acts are those directed at the mind and not the body, but activities like 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 865 leads to tangible, physical changes in society only indirectly when people choose to act on that speech.311 The emotional effects of speech are not considered equivalent to the direct, external changes incurred from conduct.312 Scholars argue that the distinction between speech and conduct is artificial and unworkable,313 but assessing this divide in emotional/physical terms has significant explanatory power. Consider expressive conduct, which is conduct relating to the physical world that serves to communicate ideas.314 The government can regulate this expressive conduct so long as the law furthers a significant government interest that is unrelated to the expression of ideas.315 Thus, the government can proscribe destroying a draft card if the physical act of destruction affects the administrability of the draft system, but not because of the emotional and psychic effects of the message.316 The view that the physical/emotional divide underlies the distinction between protected speech and unprotected conduct is strengthened when psychotropic-drug use and subliminal advertising are directed at the mind and still not protected from regulation.” (footnote omitted)). Greenman’s dismissal of the connection between the mind/body distinction and the speech/conduct distinction falls short, however. The regulation of psychotropic drugs, which he believes affect only the mind, may also be based on the drugs’ physical effects on the body. Further, these regulations control the physical act of selling or taking the drug. As for regulations on subliminal advertising, all advertising, as commercial speech, is subject to less speech protection. 311 See Sullivan, supra note 310, at 976 (“Normally, if speech offends your sensibilities or causes you anger, resentment, or alarm, the free speech consensus says your solution is not to call the sheriff but to turn the other cheek.”). 312 See Wendy B. Reilly, Fighting the Fighting Words Standard: A Call for Its Destruction, 52 RUTGERS L. REV. 947, 958–59 (2000) (arguing in favor of eliminating the protection for certain types of hurtful speech and claiming that “[t]he Supreme Court has constructed a false dichotomy between physical and emotional pain as it relates to the regulation of speech and conduct through the fighting words doctrine”). 313 See, e.g., LAURENCE H. TRIBE, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 827 (2d ed. 1988) (“The trouble with the distinction between speech and conduct is that it has less determinate content than is sometimes supposed.”); Louis Henkin, Foreword: On Drawing Lines, 82 HARV. L. REV. 63, 79 (1968) (“A constitutional distinction between speech and nonspeech has no content. A constitutional distinction between speech and conduct is specious. Speech is conduct, and actions speak.”); Stephanie M. Kaufman, The Speech/Conduct Distinction and First Amendment Protection of Begging in Subways, 79 GEO. L.J. 1803, 1821 (1991) (claiming that a distinction between speech and conduct in First Amendment jurisprudence is, inter alia, “inevitably false”); Laurie Magid, First Amendment Protection of Ambiguous Conduct, 84 COLUM. L. REV. 467, 474 (1984) (asserting that the Supreme Court’s distinction between speech and conduct in cases involving expressive activity is tenuous). 314 See United States v. O’Brien, 391 U.S. 367, 376 (1968) (describing expressive conduct, also known as “symbolic speech,” as “communication of ideas by conduct” (internal quotation marks omitted)). 315 See id. at 377 (“[G]overnment regulation is sufficiently justified if it . . . furthers an important or substantial governmental interest . . . .”). 316 See id. at 377–78 (concluding that the U.S. government’s draft card registration system furthers a significant government interest insofar as the system serves as a “substantial administrative aid” for the exercise of Congress’s constitutional war powers and that legislation upholding this system passes constitutional muster). 866 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 examining the exceptions to speech protections. Many categories of speech that are unprotected, like true threats, fighting words, or even the classic example of yelling “fire” in a crowded theater, are bound up in the protection of bodily integrity or against fear of imminent bodily injury.317 Even the ban on child pornography is justified by the fact that child pornography is “‘intrinsically related’ to the sexual abuse of children.”318 Some types of speech that have been deemed unprotected, like obscenity, libel, invasion of privacy, or hostile work environment harassment, do not directly concern harms to bodily integrity. However, courts justify their removal from protected status largely based on effects or interests that are unrelated to emotional harm, and are sometimes related to the body. Obscenity was originally deemed unprotected because it caused a “form of immorality which has relation to sexual impurity” based on its “tendency to excite lustful thoughts.”319 Libel concerns a reputational interest and often also has an economic component.320 For sexual harassment under Title IX to be unprotected, it must be so severe and pervasive as to deny a plaintiff an educational opportunity, a separate important interest.321 First Amendment law’s protections thus complement, and essentially depend on, the hierarchy of physical and emotional harm in tort law. First Amendment law goes even further than tort law: it prohibits the government from intervening when the primary harms resulting from the speech are emotional and are unrelated to bodily integrity or other, significant interests. If the physical/emotional distinction collapsed, our strong free speech protections would likely be seriously compromised, at least in theory if not in practice. 317 See, e.g., Virginia v. Black, 538 U.S. 343, 359 (2003) (“‘True threats’ encompass those statements where the speaker means to communicate a serious expression of an intent to commit an act of unlawful violence to a particular individual or group of individuals.”); Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15, 20 (1971) (holding that fighting words, or “those personally abusive epithets which, when addressed to the ordinary citizen, are, as a matter of common knowledge, inherently likely to provoke violent reaction” are unprotected). 318 Ashcroft v. Free Speech Coal., 535 U.S. 234, 249 (2002) (quoting New York v. Ferber, 458 U.S. 747, 759 (1982)). 319 Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. 476, 486 (1957). 320 See supra Part III.A (discussing the traditional tort doctrines and their treatment of the distinction between physical and emotional harm). 321 Davis v. Monroe Cnty. Bd. of Educ., 526 U.S. 629, 633 (1999) (“Moreover, we conclude that such an action will lie only for harassment that is so severe, pervasive, and objectively offensive that it effectively bars the victim’s access to an educational opportunity or benefit.”). To survive First Amendment scrutiny, a hostile work environment sexual harassment claim must allege conduct that is so severe and pervasive that it creates an abusive work environment. See Eugene Volokh, What Speech Does “Hostile Work Environment” Harassment Law Restrict?, 85 GEO. L.J. 627, 628 (1997) (providing the basic elements for speech to be punishable as workplace harassment). 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 867 b. The Physical/Emotional Distinction in Criminal Law and the Voluntariness Component of Fifth Amendment Doctrine In criminal law, the element of “bodily injury” is an important way in which courts distinguish between criminal and non-criminal conduct.322 Further, in the context of the Fifth Amendment’s right against selfincrimination, courts have given police officers wider latitude to manipulate suspects emotionally than to threaten them physically. To the extent that uniformity in the law is a virtue, a tort duty to regulate one’s own emotional health reasonably finds support in criminal law as well. The term “bodily injury is an element in defining crimes”—including menacing, simple assault, unlawful arrest, resisting arrest, aggravated kidnapping, and aggravated robbery.323 Although state criminal codes vary, the vast majority of states do not include mental injury or impairment within the definition of “bodily injury.”324 “The most common definition of bodily injury . . . is ‘physical pain, illness, or any impairment of physical condition.’”325 Other states include language specifying how severe a physical injury must be or the types of physical marks needed.326 Montana, one of the few states to include mental injury within the category of bodily injury, defines bodily injury as “physical pain, illness, or an impairment of physical condition . . . includ[ing] mental illness or impairment.”327 Thus, although different from tort law in scope and purpose, criminal law also properly distinguishes between bodily injury and emotional harm, prioritizing bodily harm as more worthy of protection. The Fifth Amendment’s right against self-incrimination also privileges bodily injury over emotional distress. The Fifth Amendment protects criminal defendants against coerced confessions.328 In determining whether physical or emotional manipulation during police interrogations is unconstitutional, Fifth Amendment doctrine grounds analysis in the concept of voluntariness. Confessions violate the Fifth Amendment only to the extent that they are involuntary,329 or not a product of a “free and 322 See Shen, supra note 21, at 2044 (“In a variety of criminal and quasi-criminal contexts, this legislative line drawing between criminal and non-criminal behavior invokes the concept of ‘bodily’ (or ‘physical’) injury.”). 323 Id. at 2045–46. 324 Id. at 2048. 325 Id. at 2047. 326 Id. at 2047–48 (discussing the variations in the standard for physical injuries across states). 327 MONT. CODE ANN. § 45-2-101 (West 2013); Shen, supra note 21, at 2048 (internal quotation marks omitted). 328 See U.S. CONST. amend. V (“No person . . . shall be compelled in any criminal case to be a witness against himself . . . .”). 329 See Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436, 464 n.33 (1965) (“It is now axiomatic that the defendant’s constitutional rights have been violated if his conviction is based, in whole or in part, on an involuntary confession, regardless of its truth or falsity.”); Bram v. United States, 168 U.S. 532, 542 (1897) (adopting voluntariness as a constitutional requirement for admissibility of confessions). 868 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 330 rational will.” A confession is considered involuntary when a defendant’s will is overborne due to coercive questions, physical mistreatment, or emotional manipulation.331 Although courts and scholars have fared no better than philosophers in confronting issues related to voluntariness and free will in the Fifth Amendment context,332 some instructive guidelines have emerged that roughly track common sense experience with consciousness, the physical/emotional distinction in tort doctrine, the “agency concern” in civil recourse theory, and notions of free will in corrective justice. As in other legal disciplines, physical compulsion is considered more corrosive to free will than emotional harm. Suspects subjected to physical violence are automatically considered to be acting involuntarily, whereas “psychological coercion provokes no per se rule.”333 Just the fear of physical violence from even a non-state actor renders a confession involuntary, if a government agent is exploiting that fear.334 Physical confinement—where a suspect is not free to leave a police station—causes a confession to be presumptively involuntary unless Miranda warnings, informing a suspect of her right to remain silent and receive an attorney, are given.335 Emotional or psychological pressures become a Fifth Amendment violation only when the government’s actions, not the subjective infirmities of the suspect, overbear the will of the suspect.336 The mental sophistication and emotional state of the defendant are relevant in cases of psychological coercion only if known to and exploited by the police.337 Deception is permitted unless it rises to the level of overbearing the will of 330 See Richard A. Leo, The Impact of Miranda Revisited, 86 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 621, 625 (1996) (“Only confessions that were the product of a free and rational will were admissible.”). 331 Specifically, courts analyzing the voluntariness of a confession ask “whether a defendant’s will was overborne by the circumstances surrounding the giving of a confession.” Dickerson v. United States, 530 U.S. 428, 434 (2000) (internal quotation marks omitted). 332 Mark A. Godsey, Rethinking the Involuntary Confession Rule: Toward a Workable Test for Identifying Compelled Self-Incrimination, 93 CALIF. L. REV. 465, 468–70 (2005). 333 United States v. Miller, 984 F.2d 1028, 1030 (9th Cir. 1993). 334 See Arizona v. Fulminante, 499 U.S. 279, 288 (1991) (finding a confession coerced because “it was fear of physical violence, absent protection from his friend (and Government agent) Sarivola, which motivated Fulminante to confess”). 335 Charles D. Weisselberg, Mourning Miranda, 96 CALIF. L. REV. 1519, 1525 (2008). 336 See Colorado v. Connelly, 479 U.S. 157, 170–71 (1986) (explaining that the rationale of the Court’s holding in Miranda was based on governmental coercion and, if the Court held that a waiver of Miranda rights constituted coercion for any other reason, it would be overreaching beyond the holding in Miranda and the Constitution). 337 See Smith v. Mullin, 379 F.3d 919, 934–35 (10th Cir. 2004) (admitting the confession of a defendant whose “cognitive abilities were similar to those of a twelve-year-old” because the police questioned him slowly and did not exploit his cognitive impairments). In Part V, I will argue that this type of analysis should also be used in the tort context when dealing with emotional harm. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 869 338 the suspect. The police may lie about the strength of the evidence, may falsely flatter the defendant, and may understate the moral reprehensibility of the crime in an attempt to procure a confession.339 Psychological manipulation does not render a confession involuntary in the same way as threats of violence or physical force.340 Legal doctrine in the criminal law context also relies on the divide between physical and emotional harm. Emotional harm is considered akin to physical harm only in limited cases. Just as in tort law and free speech doctrine, this distinction is based on notions of responsibility, agency, and social utility. Yet there are certain cases where the hierarchy does and should collapse because a duty to maintain one’s emotional health is properly exercised. V. IMPLICATIONS AND DOCTRINAL MODIFICATIONS Responsive to criticisms of the physical/emotional distinction, a new conception of the duties that we owe to protect ourselves and others from emotional harm is consistent with much of existing doctrine. Further attempts to expand emotional duties to others, however, should be considered in light of this new conception. Without devaluing the significance of emotional harm, the previous Section argued against a general duty to protect others from emotional injury, based on a duty to maintain our own emotional health.341 However, there should be limitations to this duty to protect oneself. The justifications for a categorical physical/emotional distinction do not hold in certain situations. This Section explores exceptions to the general duty to maintain one’s emotional health and how to handle cases where an event causes both physical and emotional injury. A. Emotional Duties and Eggshell Psyches A duty to maintain and control one’s emotional health would require individuals to reasonably handle their emotional responses, both before and after distressing events. This duty justifies most courts’ rejection of the 338 See Illinois v. Perkins, 496 U.S. 292, 297 (1990) (“Miranda forbids coercion, not mere strategic deception by taking advantage of a suspect’s misplaced trust . . . . Ploys to mislead a suspect or lull him into a false sense of security that do not rise to the level of compulsion or coercion to speak are not within Miranda’s concerns.”). 339 Christopher Slobogin, Lying and Confessing, 39 TEX. TECH L. REV. 1275, 1282 (2007). 340 See Captain Frederic I. Lederer, The Law of Confessions—The Voluntariness Doctrine, 74 MIL. L. REV. 67, 82 (1976) (explaining that determining the involuntariness of confessions which are psychologically manipulated are more difficult to make and will “depend upon the character and background of the suspect”). 341 See supra Part IV.B. (arguing that we should be subject to a legal duty to maintain our emotions and that legal obligations to protect others should therefore be limited, particularly in tort law). 870 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 342 “eggshell psyche” rule. Plaintiffs are compensated for emotional injury only if the emotional injury results from conduct that would cause an ordinarily constituted person to suffer such an injury.343 The seriousness requirement ensures that plaintiffs are compensated only after they have exercised their own duty to tolerate and handle emotional upset, and the reasonableness requirement ensures that plaintiffs are held to a uniform standard when doing so.344 Just as we require defendants to exercise a reasonable duty of care to avoid causing others physical harm regardless of defendants’ capacities,345 plaintiffs should be required to adjust and adapt to life’s upsets reasonably, and to seek help for pre-existing conditions that might render them “unreasonably” susceptible to emotional distress. Compensating emotional injuries only in cases where a plaintiff reasonably suffers serious emotional harm does penalize those who are more sensitive yet undertake valiant efforts to manage emotional harm. As mentioned above, this unfortunate effect is based on a unitary standard that is not unlike holding defendants of varying capacities to an objective standard of care. It is also necessary both conceptually and practically. From a prudential standpoint, it is difficult to determine and prove which plaintiffs are hypersensitive. Plaintiffs would have increased incentive to depict themselves as possessing less capacity for emotional control. Conceptually, the virtues of establishing a duty to exercise reasonable care of one’s own emotional health, much like the duty to exercise reasonable care to avoid causing harm to others, requires courts to maintain a unified standard. Holding everyone to the same standard of reasonable emotional responses cultivates beliefs in self-help and agency, allows for optimal autonomy of defendants, and comports with various tort law theories, as well as doctrines in other legal disciplines.346 Defendants can rely on possessing spheres of autonomy in which they do not have to worry about modifying their behavior in deference to others’ emotional wellbeing. 342 See Thierault v. Swan, 558 A.2d 369, 372 (Me. 1989) (“When the harm reasonably could affect only the hurt feelings of the supersensitive plaintiff—the eggshell psyche—there is no entitlement to recovery.”). 343 See supra notes 81–82 and accompanying text (noting that for emotional harms to be compensable, they must meet a seriousness requirement and they must be the kind of harms that an ordinary person would have suffered). 344 Id. 345 See Kenneth W. Simons, The Restatement (Third) of Torts and Traditional Strict Liability: Robust Rationales, Slender Doctrines, 44 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 1355, 1379 (2009) (“The objective test of reasonable care formally imposes a duty of care even on those who lack the mental capacity to satisfy that duty.”). 346 See supra Part IV (describing, inter alia, the challenges to maintaining the physical/emotional distinction and the support for the distinction). 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 871 347 However, as in the Fifth Amendment context, unreasonable emotional distress could be compensable in certain situations if a defendant knew about and exploited the plaintiff’s psychological or emotional infirmities. For example, if an employer purposely treated a psychologically vulnerable employee differently and caused serious emotional distress, this should be compensable because the employer’s change in behavior falls outside the sphere of autonomy that the physical/emotional distinction promotes. Thus, an eggshell psyche rule, which would allow plaintiffs to assert emotional injury based on their subjective distress even if they are hypersensitive, should not apply to the duty inquiry for either negligent or intentional infliction of emotional distress. Further, even if a plaintiff demonstrates that he reasonably suffered serious injury, he should receive damages only to the extent that a reasonable person would require compensation. Thus, unlike the current state of the law, a rejection of the eggshell psyche rule should apply not just at the duty inquiry—when determining whether a defendant can be held liable at all—but also at the damages inquiry. Individuals can then navigate the world without having to account for emotional responses that are unreasonably severe. B. Compensable Emotional Injuries Even after exercising a reasonable amount of control over his emotional state, there are situations where a plaintiff would experience serious emotional distress. Our emotional duty to ourselves becomes less relevant when psychological distress compromises our voluntary ability to exert emotional control or is bound up in either promotion of bodily integrity or some other independent and protectable interest,348 which is protected by a separate duty imposed on the defendant. In cases where most people would become emotionally distraught to the point of needing care or treatment, an emotional injury should be compensable, if the recognition of the emotional harm does not unduly compromise the autonomy rights of either party.349 347 Cf. supra Part IV.B.3.b. (discussing “the context of the Fifth Amendment’s right against selfincrimination” and how courts often permit police officers to manipulate criminal suspects emotionally). 348 See Dianne M. Tice et al., Emotional Distress Regulation Takes Precedence Over Impulse Control: If You Feel Bad, Do It!, 80 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 53, 54 (2001) (“Ample evidence has indicated that self-regulation (especially impulse control) tends to deteriorate during periods of emotional distress.”). 349 An example of this would be courts’ refusal to compensate emotional injuries in cases where protected speech is at issue. See Snyder v. Phelps, 131 S. Ct. 1207, 1220 (2010) (involving protected speech). Even some cases involving sexual harassment may infringe too far into the speech interests of the defendant. See Volokh, supra note 321, at 647 (concluding that harassment law burdens workplace 872 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 When an event is so distressing that it overtakes a plaintiff’s ability to temper his own emotions, tort law does provide redress for plaintiffs.350 As Goldberg and Zipursky note, “[t]here are situations in which a reasonable person cannot be expected to keep a stiff upper lip; she cannot be expected to avoid responding by tumbling into severe emotional distress, that is, situations in which the mountain is a mountain, not a molehill.”351 This is why negligent infliction of emotional distress and intentional infliction of emotional distress claims allow compensation for injuries in certain cases that are likely to provoke a reasonable person to serious emotional injury.352 It will be difficult for courts to determine when a plaintiff has properly exercised his duty to manage his own emotional health and is nonetheless still suffering from serious emotional injury. Courts should start by considering cases where an independent duty of care (owed to something other than plaintiff’s emotional well being) is breached by the defendant. First, courts should recognize that the protection of bodily integrity is a primary concern of tort law, given the physical/emotional distinction.353 Emotional injuries that stem from fear of one’s life or physical safety, and perhaps the physical safety of others, are more likely to be reasonable, in both an empirical and a normative sense.354 Courts could even reframe these emotional injuries as injuries caused by a defendant’s breach of her duty to take care not to cause physical harm to the plaintiff. Although no physical harm results,355 the defendant has negligently placed the plaintiff’s bodily integrity in jeopardy, leading to serious emotional injuries like fright and anxiety. Thus, if the defendant negligently hits the plaintiff’s automobile in a way that reasonably causes the plaintiff emotional trauma, the defendant should compensate the plaintiff for these emotional injuries, to the extent that they are reasonable. speech even though speech may be political or not severe or pervasive enough). The emotional duty to temper our own emotional states could thus include a normative, as well as an empirical, component. 350 Goldberg and Zipursky explain that fright from fear of a bullet whizzing past one’s head or an automobile accident provokes a response that is “visceral, immediate, and unthinking. In this context, it makes little sense to hold the plaintiff responsible for the response and makes much more sense to think of the plaintiff as a victim who exercised little or no agency.” Goldberg & Zipursky, Unrealized Torts, supra note 8, at 1685–86. 351 Id. at 1687. 352 See supra text accompanying note 77 (“Most courts bar recovery for stand-alone emotional injury, like negligent infliction of emotional distress, unless a defendant’s actions are of a sort that would cause serious emotional distress, even to a person of reasonable or ordinary resilience.”). 353 See supra note 71 and accompanying text (“Tort law is less willing to protect emotional injuries that are unrelated to either bodily integrity or to an independent, non-emotional interest.”). 354 Indeed, some courts have held that “while physical injury is no longer a necessary element of a cause of action to recover damages for negligent infliction of emotional distress, such a cause of action must generally be premised upon conduct that unreasonably endangers the plaintiff’s physical safety.” Losquadro v. Winthrop Univ. Hosp., 216 A.D.2d 533, 534 (N.Y. App. Div. 1995). 355 If physical harm resulted, the plaintiff would primarily be suing for a physical injury. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 873 Further, if some other independently recognized interest of the plaintiff’s is harmed, and the plaintiff reasonably suffers emotional injury as a result, there are cases where the plaintiff should be compensated for those emotional injuries. This would cover interests like libel, workplace harassment, and discrimination, if state law independently protects these interests. Although courts should fully protect these interests qua interests, courts should be less protective of the emotional harms stemming from these interests. Courts should consider whether it is reasonable to suffer serious emotional injury and the extent of the injury it is reasonable to suffer in these types of cases. There will be instances where plaintiffs may reasonably be expected not to suffer serious emotional injury, for example, once their interests are vindicated, their economic losses are compensated, and their jobs are restored. Tort law should not concern itself with generally protecting emotional tranquility. Thus, in cases where an interest can be vindicated, this vindication should be the court’s primary goal. However, if an interest cannot be vindicated, courts should allow emotional distress damages to the extent that they are reasonably serious. For example, a court allowed emotional distress damages against a store for negligently reporting to the police that a customer was counterfeiting money.356 The interest in not being falsely arrested and imprisoned overnight could not be vindicated, so emotional distress damages in that case both compensate for the emotional injury and serve to vindicate the interest.357 Cases involving violations of independent interests, leading to emotional harm, differ from the cases above where bodily integrity was put in jeopardy, causing emotional harm. In the latter cases, the interest in bodily integrity cannot be vindicated because no physical harm has occurred. This approach would leave intact a good deal of the Restatement’s treatment of emotional injuries,358 although bystander liability could be limited or expanded, depending on a court’s view of the desirability of rules versus standards. The Restatement’s approach to negligently-inflicted emotional distress carves out rules for when bystanders can receive compensation for their emotional injuries.359 These rules are likely 356 Pool v. City of Oakland, 728 P.2d 1163, 1176 (Cal. 1986). Cf., Drew Alan Hillier, Note, The Necessity of an Equity and Comity Analysis In Younger Abstention Doctrine, 46 CONN. L. REV. 1975, 1983 (2014) (“[O]nce a criminal charge has been publically levied, the harm that the charge alone causes cannot be compensated for by damages.”). 358 See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 47 (2012) (recommending that the actor who causes emotional harm to another because of negligent conduct should be subject to liability if they “place[] the other in danger of immediate bodily harm and the emotional harm results from [that] or [it] occurs in the course of specified categories of activities . . . . where negligent conduct is likely to cause serious emotional harm”). 359 Currently, bystanders to the infliction of serious bodily harm to another can recover if the bystander “(a) perceives the event contemporaneously, and (b) is a close family member of the person 357 874 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 intended to approximate situations where the worst emotional harm occurs. Courts could also use a voluntariness standard instead of applying categorical rules, allowing compensation for bystanders’ emotional distress in cases where a reasonable person’s capacity in tempering emotional responses would be compromised. Or, courts could rely on bright line rules establishing stricter (no bystander liability unless the plaintiff’s safety was directly jeopardized) or less strict (all bystanders who witness death or serious physical injury of a familiar party) rules for compensation. Any of these approaches would be consistent with adherence to a physical/emotional hierarchy based on a duty to exercise care for one’s own emotional health, and the right approach would depend on a court’s views of the ability to administer fairness and justice, not to mention other pragmatic concerns like crushing liability and limited funds. In negligence cases, to demonstrate that a bystander’s emotional distress reasonably compromised voluntariness in cases where no duty of physical safety has been breached, however, the plaintiff should be required to show a clinically diagnosable mental health condition.360 This extra requirement, which would limit potentially expansive bystander claims and focus on those for whom bodily integrity was jeopardized, should not exist in cases where the defendant has breached a separate duty to the plaintiff’s physical safety, as in the automobile example above. It should attach only when the defendant has solely breached a duty to plaintiff’s emotional well-being. In cases where a duty to exercise reasonable care to protect the plaintiff’s physical safety has been breached, even if the plaintiff suffered no physical injuries, he should be required to show only that he reasonably suffered serious emotional distress. In this way, the physical/emotional hierarchy is preserved by privileging those whose emotional injuries stem from defendant’s jeopardizing their physical integrity, while also allowing those who have reasonably experienced serious emotional injury to be compensated. Thus, at the duty stage, one approach would be to require plaintiffs to demonstrate an emotional injury that is either severe or clinically significant to the extent of reasonably compromising voluntariness, or serious and closely related to jeopardizing a plaintiff’s physical integrity or an interest that cannot be fully vindicated. Plaintiffs should also demonstrate that the extent of their damages is reasonable, and not greater suffering the bodily injury.” RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL & EMOTIONAL HARM § 48 (2012). 360 This is what Betsy Grey would require for compensation of all emotional injuries. See supra Part III.A. (describing Betsy Grey as a proponent for the English unitary view of tort law, which abolishes the distinction and treats emotional harm as an aspect of bodily harm). She, however, would disband with any of the other heightened pleading requirements for emotional distress, and would likely not endorse a duty to maintain one’s own emotional health. 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 875 than the extent a reasonable person would experience. In allowing for compensation of certain types of emotional injuries, courts should recognize that, as noted by those who wish to blur the physical/emotional distinction, emotional harm increasingly can be proven. Courts should create standards for assessing and demonstrating emotional harm as technology improves and mental illness becomes better understood. C. Parasitic Physical and Emotional Damages A duty to reasonably regulate one’s own emotional health would alter how courts treat parasitic injuries—emotional damages that flow from physical injury or the violation of an independent interest—in addition to physical injuries that flow from the violation of one’s emotional tranquility. Unlike current doctrine, when a physical injury causes emotional harm or pain and suffering, a plaintiff’s parasitic emotional injuries should still be subject to the requirement that they be reasonably serious.361 If what separates physical injury from emotional injury is a duty to regulate one’s own emotional health, this duty should apply equally to parasitic damages for emotional injury as to claims for stand-alone emotional injury. In the case of parasitic damages, it will be relatively easy to demonstrate a reasonably serious emotional injury, especially if the physical injury is serious. However, because the emotional losses from physical injury are usually less enduring than people think,362 perhaps plaintiffs’ emotional damages should be limited in time, at which point they will no longer need treatment or intervention for their emotional injuries. To the extent that physical pain persists, and to the extent that damages for “suffering” captures the intangible costs of lost capabilities, these damages should not be limited in time.363 This Article departs most dramatically from the Restatement in its approach to physical harms that result from emotional distress. The 361 Many courts allow damages for all of a plaintiff’s emotional distress and pain and suffering consequent to a physical injury. See Bligh v. Travelers Home & Marine Ins. Co., No. HHDCV106016059S, 2013 WL 4421312, at *9 (Conn. Super. Ct. July 29, 2013) (“A plaintiff who is injured by the negligence of another is entitled to be compensated for all physical pain and suffering, mental and emotional suffering, loss of the ability to enjoy life’s pleasures, and permanent impairment or loss of function that she proves by a fair preponderance of the evidence to have been proximately caused by the negligence of another.”). 362 See supra Part III.B. (“[I]ndividuals often overestimate the hedonic losses from physical injuries . . . . because ‘human beings are unexpectedly resilient . . . .’”). 363 There is significant debate about how best to calculate pain and suffering damages. Some scholars propose awarding damages to tort plaintiffs, even if they have hedonically adjusted to physical injuries, based on lost capabilities. See, e.g., Rick Swedloff & Peter H. Huang, Tort Damages and the New Science of Happiness, 85 IND. L.J. 553, 577–80 (2010) (arguing that none of these awards are granted without consideration of adaptation, even if implicitly); see generally MARTHA NUSSBAUM & AMARTYA SEN, THE QUALITY OF LIFE (1993). 876 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 47:809 Restatement provides that bodily injury that results from emotional distress should be treated as a physical injury, and thus not subject to the heightened pleading requirements of reasonableness and severity that attach to stand-alone emotional harm.364 However, given an emotional duty to ourselves, only physical injury that reasonably results from emotional injury should be compensated. If a pregnant woman miscarries because she experiences extreme fear from a negligently caused accident, her fear response is likely reasonable, especially if her physical safety was placed in jeopardy. But, if someone commits suicide after being subject to extremely limited libel, or mild workplace harassment, or perhaps even after witnessing a minor accident that injured another, courts may well consider this an unreasonable emotional response, even though it led to bodily injury; nonetheless the Restatement would treat it as a bodily injury.365 While tragic, the unanticipated and extreme responses of the emotionally and psychologically vulnerable should not be taxable to defendants unless they purposely exploited this vulnerability. The reasonableness component of the emotional duty to oneself should thus also attach to bodily injury that is brought about solely through the medium of emotional harm. This treatment of physical harms that cause emotional harms, and emotional harms that result in physical harms, would unify the law’s conceptualization of the physical/emotional distinction, even in areas where both harms are at issue. Breaches of emotional integrity should be treated differently than breaches of physical integrity. Because of a duty to maintain one’s emotional health, heightened requirements should apply at the liability and damages stages for emotional injuries or at instances where physical safety is not placed in jeopardy. Physical injuries that arise through the medium of emotional injuries should also be subject to reasonableness requirements, but if they are based on jeopardizing the plaintiff’s physical integrity they will generally be considered reasonable. Physical injuries that arise through impact or physical trauma are not subject to heightened pleading requirements, and are afforded the eggshell plaintiff rule, and emotional injuries that result therefrom will generally be considered reasonable. A duty to avoid causing others physical harm exists generally, whereas a duty to avoid causing others emotional injury exists only in limited cases. 364 Supra notes 76–77 and accompanying text. More should be said here about bullying, especially bullying of children, or bullying of children by children, but that is beyond the scope of this Article, especially as children are held to different standards of care in tort law, see Presumptions Based on Age, 42 AM. JUR. 2D Infants § 127 (2010), and thus should also be held to different emotional duties to maintain their own emotional health. 365 2015] EMOTIONAL DUTIES 877 VI. CONCLUSION This Article has begun to establish theoretical justifications for the physical/emotional distinction in tort law. Imposing an emotional duty to maintain one’s own emotional health would not only explain and justify a good deal of tort law, it would unify its principles with other legal disciplines. Ultimately, this duty would benefit both plaintiffs and defendants and send a message that emotional health is serious, that it must be tended to prior to traumatic events, and that it can be within our own control.
© Copyright 2024